Segment 1 Of 2     Next Hearing Segment(2)

SPEAKERS       CONTENTS       INSERTS    Tables

 Page 1       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
59–929

2000
RELIGIOUS LIBERTY PROTECTION ACT OF 1998

HEARINGS

BEFORE THE

SUBCOMMITTEE ON THE CONSTITUTION

OF THE
COMMITTEE ON THE JUDICIARY
HOUSE OF REPRESENTATIVES

ONE HUNDRED FIFTH CONGRESS

SECOND SESSION

ON
H.R. 4019

JUNE 16 AND JULY 14, 1998

Serial No. 134
 Page 2       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

Printed for the use of the Committee on the Judiciary

For sale by the U.S. Government Printing Office
Superintendent of Documents, Congressional Sales Office, Washington, DC 20402

COMMITTEE ON THE JUDICIARY
HENRY J. HYDE, Illinois, Chairman
F. JAMES SENSENBRENNER, Jr., Wisconsin
BILL McCOLLUM, Florida
GEORGE W. GEKAS, Pennsylvania
HOWARD COBLE, North Carolina
LAMAR SMITH, Texas
ELTON GALLEGLY, California
CHARLES T. CANADY, Florida
BOB INGLIS, South Carolina
BOB GOODLATTE, Virginia
STEPHEN E. BUYER, Indiana
ED BRYANT, Tennessee
STEVE CHABOT, Ohio
BOB BARR, Georgia
WILLIAM L. JENKINS, Tennessee
ASA HUTCHINSON, Arkansas
EDWARD A. PEASE, Indiana
CHRIS CANNON, Utah
 Page 3       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
JAMES E. ROGAN, California
LINDSEY O. GRAHAM, South Carolina
MARY BONO, California

JOHN CONYERS, Jr., Michigan
BARNEY FRANK, Massachusetts
CHARLES E. SCHUMER, New York
HOWARD L. BERMAN, California
RICK BOUCHER, Virginia
JERROLD NADLER, New York
ROBERT C. SCOTT, Virginia
MELVIN L. WATT, North Carolina
ZOE LOFGREN, California
SHEILA JACKSON LEE, Texas
MAXINE WATERS, California
MARTIN T. MEEHAN, Massachusetts
WILLIAM D. DELAHUNT, Massachusetts
ROBERT WEXLER, Florida
STEVEN R. ROTHMAN, New Jersey

THOMAS E. MOONEY, General Counsel-Chief of Staff
JULIAN EPSTEIN, Minority Staff Director

Subcommittee on the Constitution
CHARLES T. CANADY, Florida, Chairman
 Page 4       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
HENRY J. HYDE, Illinois
BOB INGLIS, South Carolina
ED BRYANT, Tennessee
WILLIAM L. JENKINS, Tennessee
BOB GOODLATTE, Virginia
BOB BARR, Georgia
ASA HUTCHINSON, Arkansas

ROBERT C. SCOTT, Virginia
MAXINE WATERS, California
JOHN CONYERS, Jr., Michigan
JERROLD NADLER, New York
MELVIN L. WATT, North Carolina

JOHN H. LADD, Acting Chief Counsel
ROBERT J. CORRY, Counsel
CATHLEEN CLEAVER, Counsel

C O N T E N T S

HEARING DATES
    June 16, 1998
    July 14, 1998

BILL TEXT
 Page 5       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    H.R. 4019

OPENING STATEMENT

    Canady, Charles T., a Representative in Congress from the State of Florida, and chairman, Subcommittee on the Constitution

WITNESSES

    Berg, Thomas C., Professor, Cumberland Law School, Samford University

    Dodson, William, Director, Government Relations, Southern Baptist Convention

    Durham, W. Cole, Jr., Brigham Young University Law School

    Eisgruber, Christopher L., Professor, New York University School of Law

    Farris, Michael P., President, Home School Legal Defense Association

    Green, Steven K., Legal Director, Americans United for Separation of Church and State

    Hamilton, Marci, Professor, Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law, Yeshiva University
 Page 6       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Ivory, Reverend Elenora Giddings, Director, Washington Office, Presbyterian Church (USA)

Laycock, Douglas, Professor, Associate Dean for Research, University of Texas Law School
June 16, 1998
July 14, 1998

    Mauck, John, Attorney, Mauck, Bellande & Cheely, Chicago, IL

    May, Colby M., Senior Counsel, Office of Governmental Affairs, American Center for Law and Justice

    McFarland, Steven T., Director, Center for Law and Religious Freedom

    Nolan, Patrick, President, Justice Fellowship

    Raskin, Jamin, Professor, Washington College of Law, American University

    Schaerr, Gene, Attorney, Sidley & Austin, Washington, DC

    Shoulson, Bruce D., Attorney at Law, Lowenstein Sandler, P.C.

    Stern, Marc, Director, Legal Department, American Jewish Congress

 Page 7       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
LETTERS, STATEMENTS, ETC., SUBMITTED FOR THE HEARING

    Berg, Thomas C., Professor, Cumberland Law School, Samford University: Prepared statement

    Durham, W. Cole, Jr., Brigham Young University Law School: Prepared statement

    Eisgruber, Christopher L., Professor, New York University School of Law: Prepared statement

    Farris, Michael P., President, Home School Legal Defense Association: Prepared statement

    Green, Steven K., Legal Director, Americans United for Separation of Church and State: Prepared statement

    Hamilton, Marci, Professor, Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law, Yeshiva University: Prepared statement

    Ivory, Reverend Elenora Giddings, Director, Washington Office, Presbyterian Church (USA): Prepared statement

Laycock, Douglas, Professor, Associate Dean for Research, University of Texas Law School: Prepared statement
 Page 8       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
June 16, 1998
July 14, 1998

    McFarland, Steven T., Director, Center for Law and Religious Freedom: Prepared statement

Nadler, Hon. Jerrold, a Representative in Congress from the State of New York: Prepared statement
June 16, 1998
July 14, 1998

    Nolan, Patrick, President, Justice Fellowship: Prepared statement

    Raskin, Jamin, Professor, Washington College of Law, American University: Prepared statement

    Schaerr, Gene, Attorney, Sidley & Austin, Washington, DC: Prepared statement

    Stern, Marc, Director, Legal Department, American Jewish Congress: Prepared statement

RELIGIOUS LIBERTY PROTECTION ACT OF 1998

TUESDAY, JUNE 16, 1998

 Page 9       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
House of Representatives,
Subcommittee on the Constitution
Committee on the Judiciary,
Washington, DC.

    The subcommittee met, pursuant to call, at 10 a.m., in Room 2237, Rayburn House Office Building, Hon. Charles Canady [chairman of the subcommittee] presiding.

    Present: Representatives Charles Canady, Robert C. Scott and Jerrold Nadler.

    Staff Present: John Ladd, Chief Counsel; Robert J. Corry, Counsel; Cathleen Cleaver, Counsel; Michael Connolly, Staff Assistant; Susana Gutierrez, Clerk; and Brian Woolfolk, Minority Counsel.

OPENING STATEMENT OF CHAIRMAN CANADY

    Mr. CANADY. The subcommittee will be in order. This is the fourth hearing the subcommittee has conducted over the last year concerning the protection of religious liberty in the wake of the Boerne v. Flores decision of the Supreme Court.

    Today's hearing will focus specifically on H.R. 4019, the Religious Liberty Protection Act of 1998, legislation which Mr. Nadler and I introduced last week.
 Page 10       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    [The information referred to follows:]

105TH CONGRESS
    2D SESSION
  H. R. 4019

                              To protect religious liberty.
     
IN THE HOUSE OF REPRESENTATIVES
JUNE 9, 1998
Mr. CANADY of Florida (for himself and Mr. NADLER) introduced the following bill; which was referred to the Committee on the Judiciary
     
A BILL

                              To protect religious liberty.

    Be it enacted by the Senate and House of Representatives of the United States of America in Congress assembled,
SECTION 1. SHORT TITLE.
 Page 11       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    This Act may be cited as the ''Religious Liberty Protection Act of 1998''.
SEC. 2. PROTECTION OF RELIGIOUS EXERCISE.
    (a) GENERAL RULE.—Except as provided in subsection (b), a government shall not substantially burden a person's religious exercise—
    (1) in a program or activity, operated by a government, that receives Federal financial assistance; or
    (2) in or affecting commerce with foreign nations, among the several States, or with the Indian tribes;
even if the burden results from a rule of general applicability.     (b) EXCEPTION.—A government may substantially burden a person's religious exercise if the government demonstrates that application of the burden to the person—
    (1) is in furtherance of a compelling governmental interest; and
    (2) is the least restrictive means of furthering that compelling governmental interest.
    (c) FUNDING NOT AFFECTED.—Nothing in this section shall be construed to authorize the United States to deny or withhold Federal financial assistance as a remedy for a violation of this Act.
    (d) STATE POLICY NOT COMMANDEERED.—A government may eliminate the substantial burden on religious exercise by changing the policy that results in the burden, by retaining the policy and exempting the religious exercise from that policy, or by any other means that eliminates the burden.
    (e) DEFINITIONS.—As used in this section—
    (1) the term ''government'' means a branch, department, agency, instrumentality, subdivision, or official of a State (or other person acting under color of State law);
 Page 12       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    (2) the term ''program or activity'' means a program or activity as defined in paragraph (1) or (2) of section 606 of the Civil Rights Act of 1964 (42 U.S.C. 2000d–4a); and
    (3) the term ''demonstrates'' means meets the burdens of going forward with the evidence and of persuasion.
SEC. 3. ENFORCEMENT OF THE FREE EXERCISE CLAUSE.
    (a) PROCEDURE.—If a claimant produces prima facie evidence to support a claim of a violation of the Free Exercise Clause, the government shall bear the burden of persuasion on all issues relating to the claim, except any issue as to the existence of the burden on religious exercise.
    (b) LAND USE REGULATION.—
    (1) LIMITATION ON LAND USE REGULATION.—No government shall impose a land use regulation that—
    (A) substantially burdens religious exercise, unless the burden is the least restrictive means to prevent substantial and tangible harm to neighboring properties or to the public health or safety;
    (B) denies religious assemblies a reasonable location in the jurisdiction; or
    (C) excludes religious assemblies from areas in which nonreligious assemblies are permitted.
    (2) FULL FAITH AND CREDIT.—Adjudication of a claim of a violation of this subsection in a non-Federal forum shall be entitled to full faith and credit in a Federal court only if the claimant had a full and fair adjudication of that claim in the non-Federal forum.
    (3) NONPREEMPTION.—Nothing in this subsection shall preempt State law that is equally or more protective of religious exercise.
 Page 13       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    (4) NONAPPLICATION OF OTHER PORTIONS OF THIS ACT.—Section 2 does not apply to land use regulation.
SEC. 4. JUDICIAL RELIEF.
    (a) CAUSE OF ACTION.—A person may assert a violation of this Act as a claim or defense in a judicial proceeding and obtain appropriate relief against a government. Standing to assert a claim or defense under this section shall be governed by the general rules of standing under article III of the Constitution.
    (b) ATTORNEYS' FEES.—Section 722(b) of the Revised Statutes (42 U.S.C. 1988(b)) is amended—
    (1) by inserting ''the Religious Liberty Protection Act of 1998,'' after ''Religious Freedom Restoration Act of 1993,''; and
    (2) by striking the comma that follows a comma.
    (c) PRISONERS.—Any litigation under this Act in which the claimant is a prisoner shall be subject to the Prison Litigation Reform Act of 1995 (including provisions of law amended by that Act).
    (d) LIABILITY OF GOVERNMENTS.—
    (1) LIABILITY OF STATES.—A State shall not be immune under the 11th amendment to the Constitution from a civil action, for a violation of the Free Exercise Clause

under section 3, including a civil action for money damages.
    (2) LIABILITY OF THE UNITED STATES.—The United States shall not be immune from a civil action, for a violation of the Free Exercise Clause under section 3, including a civil action for money damages.
SEC. 5. RULES OF CONSTRUCTION.
 Page 14       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    (a) RELIGIOUS BELIEF UNAFFECTED.—Nothing in this Act shall be construed to authorize any government to burden any religious belief.
    (b) RELIGIOUS EXERCISE NOT REGULATED.—Nothing in this Act shall create any basis for regulation of religious exercise or for claims against a religious organization, including any religiously affiliated school or university, not acting under color of law.
    (c) CLAIMS TO FUNDING UNAFFECTED.—Nothing in this Act shall create or preclude a right of any religious organization to receive funding or other assistance from a government, or of any person to receive government funding for a religious activity, but this Act may require government to incur expenses in its own operations to avoid imposing a burden or a substantial burden on religious exercise.
    (d) OTHER AUTHORITY TO IMPOSE CONDITIONS ON FUNDING UNAFFECTED.—Nothing in this Act shall—
    (1) authorize a government to regulate or affect, directly or indirectly, the activities or policies of a person other than a government as a condition of receiving funding or other assistance; or
    (2) restrict any authority that may exist under other law to so regulate or affect, except as provided in this Act.
    (e) EFFECT ON OTHER LAW.—Proof that a religious exercise affects commerce for the purposes of this Act does not give rise to any inference or presumption that the religious exercise is subject to any other law regulating commerce.
    (f) SEVERABILITY.—If any provision of this Act or of an amendment made by this Act, or any application of such provision to any person or circumstance, is held to be unconstitutional, the remainder of this Act, the amendments made by this Act, and the application of the provision to any other person or circumstance shall not be affected.
 Page 15       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
SEC. 6. ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE UNAFFECTED.
    Nothing in this Act shall be construed to affect, interpret, or in any way address that portion of the first amendment to the Constitution prohibiting laws respecting an establishment of religion (referred to in this section as the ''Establishment Clause''). Granting government funding, benefits, or exemptions, to the extent permissible under the Establishment Clause, shall not constitute a violation of this Act. As used in this section, the term ''granting'', used with respect to government funding, benefits, or exemptions, does not include the denial of government funding, benefits, or exemptions.
SEC. 7. AMENDMENTS TO RELIGIOUS FREEDOM RESTORATION ACT.
    (a) DEFINITIONS.—Section 5 of the Religious Freedom Restoration Act of 1993 (42 U.S.C. 2000bb–2) is amended—
    (1) in paragraph (1), by striking ''a State, or subdivision of a State'' and inserting ''a covered entity or a subdivision of such an entity'';
    (2) in paragraph (2), by striking ''term'' and all that follows through ''includes'' and inserting ''term 'covered entity' means''; and
    (3) in paragraph (4), by striking all after ''means,'' and inserting ''an act or refusal to act that is substantially motivated by a religious belief, whether or not the act or refusal is compulsory or central to a larger system of religious belief.''.
    (b) CONFORMING AMENDMENT.—Section 6(a) of the Religious Freedom Restoration Act of 1993 (42 U.S.C. 2000bb–3(a)) is amended by striking ''and State''.
SEC. 8. DEFINITIONS.
    As used in this Act—
    (1) the term ''religious exercise'' means an act or refusal to act that is substantially motivated by a religious belief, whether or not the act or refusal is compulsory or central to a larger system of religious belief;
 Page 16       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    (2) the term ''Free Exercise Clause'' means that portion of the first amendment to the Constitution that proscribes laws prohibiting the free exercise of religion and includes the application of that proscription under the 14th amendment to the Constitution; and
    (3) except as otherwise provided in this Act, the term ''government'' means a branch, department, agency, instrumentality, subdivision, or official of a State, or other person acting under color of State law, or a branch, department, agency, instrumentality, subdivision, or official of the United States, or other person acting under color of Federal law.

    Mr. CANADY. From the outset of our history as Americans, concern about religious liberty has been central to our national experience. The bill we consider today is based on the conviction that the Congress has an ongoing responsibility to use its constitutionally established powers to protect the freedom of individual Americans to practice their faith against undue incursions by the force of government.

    It is a fact of life that the actions of government will, from time to time, come into conflict with the religious practices of some individuals and institutions. As the scope of the activities of government has grown, the occasions for such conflict have increased. The bill on which we will hear testimony today simply attempts to ensure that such conflicts will be taken seriously and that the impact of governmental action on religious freedom will be given full consideration.

    As our witnesses will explain, that does not mean that conflicts between the actions of government and the religious practices of individuals and institutions will always be resolved against the government. It does mean, however, that within the scope of the activities subject to protection by the Congress, the value of religious liberty will not be recklessly trampled by insensitive policies and thoughtless bureaucratic actions.
 Page 17       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    In America, we enjoy many important freedoms, but there is no freedom more fundamental than the freedom to practice one's faith without the interference of government. That is why we are here today, and I look forward to hearing the testimony of our witnesses who will explain the various aspects of the legislation under consideration.

    Mr. CANADY. Mr. Scott is recognized.

    Mr. SCOTT. Thank you, Mr. Chairman. And I appreciate the opportunity to participate in today's hearing on H.R. 4019, the Religious Liberty Protection Act, and I wholeheartedly agree with the bill's sponsors and their beliefs that too often certain religious practices are substantially burdened to the point where our constitutional freedoms of religious expression are compromised.

    Reverend Wilson, a minister from my district, came to one of our hearings and testified that his church was prevented from serving meals to homeless people despite the fact that feeding the hungry is a core component of his church's religious beliefs, and that legislation that prohibited churches from serving food prohibited no other group from such service. And so churches were singled out in that case, and that is one of the cases that deserve our attention and response.

    Our response, however, must be deliberate and within our authority to act. The Reverend Wilsons of the world deserve no less.

    Now, I have not signed on to the language of H.R. 4019 because I am not convinced that the bill as currently drafted can pass constitutional muster. The bill is being vetted by constitutional law experts throughout the country, and as we begin to receive responses from our inquiries, a number of very significant concerns have been raised. RFRA was overturned because the Court held that the Congress lacked authority and failed to create a proper record that would justify any congressional authority, and I am delighted that we have had hearings, and numerous hearings, on this issue and hopefully are creating a record that can help us pass constitutional muster.
 Page 18       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    The Commerce Clause, the Spending Clause and section 5 authority of RLPA have been reviewed by a number of experts that contend that the authority that we are using in H.R. 4019 may be questionable. In addition, concerns have been raised in regard to the constitutionality of State sovereign immunity and the Prison Litigation Act provisions of the bill.

    Mr. Chairman, I am delighted that we are focusing our attention to a specific bill, because it will help us focus our attention on certain—on specific language and not generalities, so that as we discuss the constitutionality, we will have the document before us.

    It is my hope that we will have a series of hearings to ensure that H.R. 4019 is constitutional and that we are creating the proper record. We have excellent witnesses testifying before us today. They are all experts in this field, and many have been very closely associated with some of the cases that have created the confusion that we are in and the cases that we have to deal with as we consider the constitutionality of this bill.

    So I want to thank you for putting together an excellent hearing, and I look forward to hearing the witnesses.

    Mr. CANADY. Thank you, Mr. Scott.

    We will now go to our first panel. I would ask that the members of the first panel please come forward and take your seats.
 Page 19       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    This morning we will hear from witnesses on two panels. Our first panel is composed of six witnesses, and the second panel will be composed of two witnesses.

    On our first panel this morning, our first witness will be Professor Douglas Laycock, who is the associate dean for research at the University of Texas Law School.

    Next will be Professor Thomas C. Berg. Professor Berg teaches at the Cumberland Law School in Birmingham, Alabama.

    Following him will be Professor Christopher L. Eisgruber of the New York University School of Law.

    The fourth witness will be Professor Marci Hamilton. Professor Hamilton comes to us from the Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law, Yeshiva University, where she specializes in constitutional law, the First Amendment and Copyright law.

    The next witness will be Mr. Gene Schaerr, who is with the law firm of Sidley & Austin in Washington, D.C.

    And our final witness on this panel will be Mr. Marc Stern. Mr. Stern is the director of the legal department at the American Jewish Congress.

    I want to thank all of you for being here with us this morning. Those of you who have been here before, I welcome you back.
 Page 20       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    I would ask that you do your best to summarize your testimony in 5 minutes or less and try to be governed by the light. When it is red, that means you should try to conclude as soon as possible.

    But without objection, of course, your full written statements will be made a part of the permanent record of the hearing.

    Mr. CANADY. With that, we will begin with Professor Laycock.

STATEMENT OF DOUGLAS LAYCOCK, PROFESSOR, ASSOCIATE DEAN FOR RESEARCH, UNIVERSITY OF TEXAS LAW SCHOOL

    Mr. LAYCOCK. Thank you, Mr. Chairman, and Mr. Scott.

    I strongly support this bill. The House unanimously concluded that a bill of this sort was necessary 5 years ago when it enacted RFRA, and now the question is what constitutional authority is available and how much of the religious liberties of the American people can Congress protect.

    I have tried to address the constitutional and scope issues in detail in my written statement. I will try to summarize the highlights here.

    First, as to the Spending Clause, the Spending Clause provisions of this bill are based squarely on the provisions in such familiar statutes as Title VI of the Civil Rights Act, Title IX on sex discrimination in education, and the Equal Access Act. The bill would ensure that the intended beneficiaries of federally-assisted programs are not excluded by unnecessary burdens on their religious exercise and would ensure that Federal funds are not spent contrary to congressional intent to unnecessarily burden religious exercise.
 Page 21       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Those purposes are at the very core of the power to attach conditions to the grant of Federal funds, and I think in all but the most unusual applications the Spending Clause provisions would pass constitutional muster.

    The Commerce Clause provisions track the language of the Clayton Act, the Federal Trade Commission Act, the Americans with Disabilities Act and many other familiar statutes. ''In or affecting commerce'' is the historic constitutional standard for what Congress can regulate. This provision is constitutional by definition.

    Religious exercise beyond the reach of the Commerce Clause is simply outside the scope of the bill. Marc Stern's testimony later today will show that religious exercise has broad commercial consequences, and on standard economic models a substantial burden on religious exercise will reduce the volume of that exercise and reduce the volume of the resulting commerce.

    I think this will have a broad range of applications. It won't reach all the religious liberty Congress would like to protect, but it will reach a very large part of it.

    Section 3 is based on the power to enforce the Fourteenth Amendment. Section 3(a) would enforce the Free Exercise Clause as interpreted by the Supreme Court. There are important parts of Employment Division v. Smith that actually do protect religious liberty, but each of those exceptions to the Smith rule poses difficult factual questions where proof is elusive, where the evidence is often in the hands of the government and where the truth is uncertain.
 Page 22       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Section 3(a) changes no element of the Supreme Court's test, but by shifting the burden of persuasion, it protects religious liberty when the case for suppression has not been fully proven.

    Section 3(b) would impose prophylactic rules on church land use regulation. The record from the earlier hearings before this committee is overwhelming that land use regulation is administered in individualized processes with few generally applicable rules; that it is rife with discrimination against religious organizations and especially against minority churches and nonmainstream churches.

    Each of these facts brings land use within one of the exceptions to the Smith rule, but these facts are very difficult to prove one case at a time. Only Congress has the ability to examine many cases and find the factual pattern that pervades across the cases. These facts support the need for section 3(b) as enacted to enforce the Fourteenth Amendment.

    The Court said in City of Boerne that Congress may act where there is reason to believe that many of the laws have a significant likelihood of being unconstitutional. The standard is not certainty. It is reason to believe and significant likelihood, and that standard is, in my judgment, easily met by this hearing record.

    With respect to prison litigation, the bill is subject to the Prison Litigation Reform Act, which is succeeding. In the first year of the Act, prisoner litigation was reduced by 31 percent. Further reductions can reasonably be expected as the bill becomes more fully effective.
 Page 23       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Mr. Scott asked about challenges to the constitutionality of that Act, and I have been following those challenges. Six circuits have upheld the Act. Only the Ninth Circuit has struck it down, and even there only with respect to retroactive reopening of final judgments. That is a very sensitive issue, but it is not an issue that would be posed by any of the interactions of the Religious Liberty Protection Act and the Prison Litigation Reform Act. The provisions on frivolous prison litigation, so far as I know, have not even been challenged; I don't think they successfully could be challenged.

    With respect to sovereign immunity, the law is fairly clear. Section 4(d) overrides the States' Eleventh Amendment immunity with respect to claims under section 3, which enforces the Fourteenth Amendment. That override is squarely authorized by Justice Rehnquist's opinion in Fitzpatrick v. Bitzer. Fitzpatrick is reaffirmed in the 1996 case of Seminole Tribe v. Florida. Seminole Tribe also holds that Congress cannot override the Eleventh Amendment in Commerce Clause legislation, and this bill does not do that. The override is squarely confined to the Fourteenth Amendment provisions.

    With respect to the Establishment Clause, the bill does not violate that Clause. The Court has unanimously held that Congress can exempt religious exercise from burdensome regulation, and that those exemptions do not have to come packaged with similar benefits for secular activities. That was the Amos decision in 1987, reaffirmed after Smith and Board of Education v. Grumet in 1994.

    Finally, I think the bill is consistent with federalism limitations on Congress' power. The bill declares a Federal policy that religious exercise should not be unnecessarily burdened. It preempts State laws that are inconsistent with that policy. The structure and effect and even the syntax of the bill's Commerce and Spending Clause provisions is indistinguishable from the structure and effect of preemption bills such as the Airline Deregulation Act. That is no coincidence. This is effectively a religion deregulation act.
 Page 24       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    The Court recognized the validity of that sort of preemptive legislation in United States v. Printz, its most recent federalism decision, when it cited with approval its earlier decisions in FERC v. Mississippi and Hodel v. Virginia. There are similar statements in New York v. United States, and all of these statements are cited fully and quoted where appropriate in my written testimony.

    I think the bill is constitutional under existing precedent. No one can predict the future, but Congress would act entirely responsibly to protect the liberties of the American people with this bill.

    Thank you, sir.

    Mr. CANADY. Thank you, Professor Laycock.

    [The prepared statement of Mr. Laycock follows:]

PREPARED STATEMENT OF DOUGLAS LAYCOCK, PROFESSOR, ASSOCIATE DEAN FOR RESEARCH, UNIVERSITY OF TEXAS LAW SCHOOL

    Thank you for the opportunity to testify this morning in support of H.R. 4019, the Religious Liberty Protection Act of 1998. This statement is submitted in my personal capacity as a scholar. I hold the Alice McKean Young Regents Chair in Law at The University of Texas at Austin, but of course The University takes no position on any issue before the Committee.
 Page 25       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    I have taught and written about the law of religious liberty, and also about a wide range of other constitutional issues, for more than twenty years. I have represented both religious organizations and secular civil liberties organizations, including important cases under the Religious Freedom Restoration Act. I wish to address Congress's constitutional authority to enact RLPA, the range of cases to which the bill might be applied, and some of the drafting choices presented by the bill.

    But first let me say a little about the importance and universality of this bill. RLPA is not a bill for left or right, or for any particular faith, or any particular tradition or faction within a faith. There is an extraordinary diversity of beliefs about religion in America, from the very far left to the very far right both theologically and politically, from the most traditional orthodoxies to the most experimental and idiosyncratic views of the supernatural. RLPA will protect people of all races, all ethnicities, and all socio-economic statuses.

    Religious liberty is a universal human right. The Supreme Court has taken the cramped view that one has a right to believe a religion, and a right not to be discriminated against because of one's religion, but no right to practice one's religion. To the extent that it has power to do so, Congress should enact more substantive protection for religious liberty.

I. THE SPENDING CLAUSE PROVISIONS.

    Section 2(a) of RLPA tracks the substantive language of the Religious Freedom Restoration Act, 42 U.S.C. §2000bb et seq. (1994), providing that government shall not substantially burden a person's religious exercise, and applies that language to cases within the spending power and the commerce power. Section 2(b) also tracks RFRA. It states the compelling interest exception to the general rule that government may not substantially burden religious exercise.
 Page 26       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Section 2(a)(1) specifies the spending power applications of RLPA. The bill applies to programs or activities operated by a government and receiving federal financial assistance. ''Government'' is defined in §2(e)(1) to include persons acting under color of state law. In general, a private-sector grantee acts under color of law only when the government retains sufficient control that ''the alleged infringement of federal rights [is] 'fairly attributable to the State.' '' Rendell-Baker v. Kohn, 457 U.S. 830, 838 (1982).

    Section 2(a)(1) would therefore protect against substantial burdens on religious exercise in programs or activities receiving federal financial assistance and operating under color of state law. It would protect a wide range of students and faculty in public schools and universities, job trainees, workfare participants, welfare recipients, tenants in public housing, and participants in many other federally assisted but state-administered programs. An individual could not be excluded from a federally assisted program because of her religious dress, or because of her observance of the Sabbath or of religious holidays, or because she said prayers over meals or at certain times during the day—unless these burdens served a compelling interest by the least restrictive means.

    The federal interest is simply that the intended beneficiaries of federal programs not be excluded because of their religious practice, and that federal funds not be used to impose unnecessary burdens on religious exercise. The provision is modeled directly on similar provisions in other civil rights laws, including Title VI of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, which forbids race discrimination in federally assisted programs, 42 U.S.C. §2000d (1994), and Title IX of the Education Amendments of 1972, which forbids sex discrimination in federally assisted educational programs, 20 U.S.C. §1681 (1994).
 Page 27       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Congressional power to attach conditions to federal spending has been consistently upheld since Steward Machine Co. v. Davis, 301 U.S. 548 (1937). Conditions on federal grants must be ''[ ]related to the federal interest in particular national projects or programs.'' South Dakota v. Dole, 483 U.S. 203, 207 (1987). Federal aid to one program does not empower Congress to demand compliance with RLPA in other programs; the bill's protections are properly confined to each federally assisted ''program or activity.'' Dole upheld a requirement that states change their drinking age as a condition of receiving federal highway funds, finding the condition directly related to safe interstate travel. Id. at 208. The connection between the federal assistance and the condition imposed on that assistance by RLPA—ensuring that the intended beneficiaries actually benefit—is even tighter than the connection in Dole. I am confident that §2(a)(1) is constitutional.

    ''Program or activity'' is defined in §2(e)(2) by incorporating a subset of the definition of the same phrase in Title VI of the Civil Rights Act of 1964. The facial constitutionality of that definition has not been seriously questioned, and I do not believe that it could be. If it turns out, in the case of some particularly sprawling state agency, that federal assistance to one part of the agency is wholly unrelated to a substantial burden on religious exercise imposed by some other and distant part of the agency, the worst case should be an as-applied challenge and a holding that the statute cannot be applied on those facts. Given the variety of ways in which agencies are structured in the fifty states, I believe that it would be difficult to draft statutory language for such unusual cases, and that they are best left to case-by-case adjudication.(see footnote 1)
 Page 28       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Section 2(c) provides that the bill does not authorize the withholding of federal funds as a remedy for violations. This provision is modeled on the Equal Access Act, another Spending Clause statute that precludes the withholding of federal funds. 20 U.S.C. §4071(e) (1994). Withholding funds is too harmful, both to the states and to the intended beneficiaries of federal assistance. Because the remedy is so harmful, it is rarely used. The individual right of action provided in §4 of RLPA is a far more appropriate remedy. States may accept or reject federal financial assistance, but if a state accepts federal assistance subject to the conditions imposed by this bill, it is obligated to fulfill the conditions and the courts may enforce that obligation. Private rights of action have been the primary and effective means of enforcement under other important Spending Clause statutes, including Title IX (see Franklin v. Gwinnett County Public Schools, 503 U.S. 60 (1992); Cannon v. University of Chicago, 441 U.S. 677 (1978)), and of course the Equal Access Act (see Board of Education v. Mergens, 496 U.S. 226 (1990).

    The rule of construction in §5(c) provides that RLPA neither creates nor precludes a right to receive funding for any religious organization or religious activity. The bill is therefore neutral on legal and political controversies over vouchers and other forms of aid to religious schools, charitable choice legislation, and other proposals for funding to religious organizations. The Coalition for the Free Exercise of Religion includes groups that disagree fundamentally on these issues, but all sides have agreed that this language is neutral and that no side's position will be undermined by this bill.

    As already noted, private-sector grantees not acting under color of law are excluded from the bill. This exclusion is important, because some private-sector grantees are religious organizations, and applying the bill to them would sometimes create conflicting rights under the same statute. The result in such cases might be to restrict religious liberty rather than protect it. Extending the bill to secular grantees in the private sector would sometimes overlap with other statutory protections, as in the employment discrimination laws and public accommodations laws. The free exercise of religion has historically been protected primarily against government action, with statutory protection extended to particular contexts where Congress or state legislatures found it necessary. This bill need not change the existing scope of protection in the private sector.
 Page 29       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

II. THE COMMERCE CLAUSE PROVISIONS.

    Section 2(a)(2) protects religious exercise ''in or affecting commerce.'' This language is taken verbatim from the Federal Trade Commission Act, and it tracks similar or identical language in the Clayton Act, the Americans with Disabilities Act, and many other statutes.(see footnote 2) This language embodies the historic constitutional standard. The bill protects all that religious exercise, and only that religious exercise, that Congress is empowered to protect. This part of the bill is constitutional by definition; any religious exercise beyond the reach of the Commerce Clause is simply outside the bill.

    In testimony prepared for this hearing, Marc Stern of the American Jewish Congress has documented some parts of the enormous volume of commerce that is based on religious exercise. This data makes clear that the activity of religious organizations substantially affects commerce; the religious exercise of these organizations is protected by the bill, subject to the compelling interest test. The religious exercise of individuals will sometimes be protected by the bill, as when religious exercise requires the use of property of a kind that is bought and sold in commerce and used in substantial quantities for religious purposes, or when an individual is denied an occupational license or a driver's license because of a religious practice.

    Substantial burdens on religious exercise prevent or deter or raise the price of religious exercise. On standard economic models, such burdens reduce the quantity of religious exercise and therefore the quantity of commerce growing out of religious exercise. Religious exercise and associated commerce that is not prevented may be diverted or distorted, which are other ways of interfering with the free flow of commerce. Congress has plenary power to protect the commerce generated by religious exercise or inhibited by substantial burdens on religious exercise, and Congress's motive for acting is irrelevant. United States v. Darby, 312 U.S. 100 (1941).
 Page 30       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Models for the Commerce Clause provisions include the Privacy Protection Act of 1980, 42 U.S.C. §2000aa (Supp. II 1996), protecting papers and documents used in preparation of a publication in or affecting commerce, which has not been challenged, the commerce clause provisions of the Federally Protected Activities Act, 18 U.S.C. 245 (1994), which the Tenth Circuit has upheld, United States v. Lane, 883 F.2d 1484, 1489–93 (10th Cir. 1989), and the public accommodations title of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, 42 U.S.C. §2000a (1994), forbidding racial and religious discrimination in places of public accommodation affecting commerce, which the Supreme Court has upheld.

    The public accommodations law is particularly instructive. Congress's first public accommodations law was the Civil Rights Act of 1875, enacted to enforce the Thirteenth and Fourteenth Amendments. The Supreme Court struck that law down as beyond the enforcement power. Civil Rights Cases, 109 U.S. 3 (1883). Congress's second public accommodations law was the Civil Rights Act of 1964, enacted with substantially the same scope in practical effect but pursuant to the commerce power. The Court upheld this Act in Katzenbach v. McClung, 379 U.S. 294 (1964), and Heart of Atlanta Motel v. United States, 379 U.S. 241 (1964).

    The public accommodations law and the Federally Protected Activities Act are also instructive in another way. Each uses a variety of federal powers to protect as much as possible of what Congress wanted to protect. The public accommodations law applies to operations that affect commerce and also to those whose discrimination is supported by state action. 42 U.S.C. §2000a(b) (1994). The Federally Protected Activities Act uses the enforcement power, the commerce power, the spending power, and power to prohibit interference with federal programs and activities (thus invoking all the powers which Congress used to create such programs and activities) to protect a broad list of activities. 18 U.S.C. §245 (1994). RLPA is more focused and less miscellaneous, but it is similar in its use of those powers that are available to protect activities in need of protection.
 Page 31       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    I have given considerable thought to United States v. Lopez, 514 U.S. 549 (1995), in which the Court struck down the Gun Free Schools Act as beyond the reach of the Commerce Clause. 18 U.S.C. §922 (1994). The offense defined in that Act was essentially a possession offense; neither purchase nor sale of the gun nor any other commercial transaction was relevant. The Court emphasized that the offense ''has nothing to do with 'commerce' or any sort of economic enterprise, however broadly one might define those terms,'' 514 U.S. at 561, and that the offense ''is in no sense an economic activity that might, through repetition elsewhere, substantially affect any sort of interstate commerce.'' Id. at 567. Lopez appears to reaffirm the long-standing rule that Congress may regulate even ''trivial'' or ''de minimis'' intrastate transactions if those transactions, ''taken together with many others similarly situated,'' substantially affect interstate commerce. Id. at 556, 558. I will refer to this rule as the aggregation rule: in considering whether an activity substantially affects commerce, Congress may aggregate large numbers of similar transactions.

    The aggregation rule is important to the scope of the bill, and especially to the protection of small churches and individuals. A small church with a RLPA claim need not show that it affects commerce all by itself; it is enough to show that churches in the aggregate affect commerce. An individual need not show that his religious practice affects commerce all by itself; it is enough to show that the practice affects commerce in the aggregate, or perhaps that a broad set of related or analogous religious practices affects commerce in the aggregate.

    There will likely be cases in which the effect on commerce cannot be proved, and which therefore fall outside the protections of the bill. That is the nearly unavoidable consequence of being forced to rely on the Commerce Clause. But there will be many cases in which the burdened religious exercise affects commerce when aggregated with ''many others similarly situated,'' Lopez, 514 U.S. at 558, and in those situations, restricting or eliminating the religious exercise by burdensome regulation would also affect commerce. I am certain that the Commerce Clause provisions are constitutional, and I am confident that they will have a wide range of applications.
 Page 32       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

III. OTHER PROVISIONS IN §2.

    Section 2(d) states explicitly what would be obvious in any event—that the government that burdens religious exercise has discretion over the means of eliminating the burden. Government can modify its policy to eliminate the burden, or adhere to its policy and grant religious exceptions where necessary to avoid imposing burdens, or make any other change that eliminates the burden. The bill would not impose any affirmative policy on the states, nor would it restrict state policy in any way whatever in secular applications or in religious applications that do not substantially burden religious exercise. The bill would require only that substantial burdens on religious exercise be eliminated or justified.

    The definition of ''demonstrates'' in §2(e)(3) is incorporated verbatim from the Religious Freedom Restoration Act.

IV. THE ENFORCEMENT CLAUSE PROVISIONS.

    Section 3 would be enacted primarily as a means of enforcing the Fourteenth Amendment. Section 3 attempts to simplify litigation of free exercise violations as defined by the Supreme Court, facilitating proof of violations in cases where proof is difficult. In some applications—church construction projects are the most obvious example—§3 could also be upheld as an exercise of the commerce power.

A. Shifting the Burden of Persuasion.

 Page 33       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    Section 3(a) provides that if a claimant demonstrates a prima facie violation of the Free Exercise Clause, the burden of persuasion then shifts to the government on all issues except burden on religious exercise. No element of the Court's definition of a free exercise violation is changed, but in cases where a court is unsure of the facts, the risk of nonpersuasion is placed on government instead of on the claim of religious liberty. This provision facilitates enforcement of the constitutional right as the Supreme Court has defined it. City of Boerne v. Flores, 117 S.Ct. 2157 (1997), of course reaffirms broad Congressional power to enforce constitutional rights as interpreted by the Supreme Court.

    This provision applies to any means of proving a free exercise violation recognized under judicial interpretations. See generally Church of the Lukumi Babalu Aye, Inc. v. City of Hialeah, 508 U.S. 520 (1993); Employment Division v. Smith, 494 U.S. 872 (1990). Thus, if the claimant shows a burden on religious exercise and prima facie evidence of an anti-religious motivation, government would bear the burden of persuasion on the question of motivation, on compelling interest, and on any other issue except burden on religious exercise. If the claimant shows a burden on religious exercise and prima facie evidence that the burdensome law is not generally applicable, government would bear the burden of persuasion on the question of general applicability, on compelling interest, and on any other issue except burden on religious exercise. If the claimant shows a burden on religion and prima facie evidence of a hybrid right, government would bear the burden of persuasion on the claim of hybrid right, including all issues except burden on religion. In general, where there is a burden on religious exercise and prima facie evidence of a constitutional violation, the risk of nonpersuasion is to be allocated in favor of protecting the constitutional right.

    The protective parts of the Smith and Lukumi rules create many difficult issues of proof and comparison. Motive is notoriously difficult to litigate, and the court is often left uncertain. The general applicability requirement means that when government exempts or fails to regulate secular activities, it must have a compelling reason for regulating religious activities that are substantially the same or that cause the same harm. See, e.g., Lukumi, 508 U.S. at 543 (''The ordinances . . . fail to prohibit nonreligious conduct that endangers these interests in a similar or greater degree''); id. at 538–39 (noting that disposal by restaurants and other sources of organic garbage created the same problems as animal sacrifice). But there can be endless arguments about whether the burdened religious activity and the less burdened secular activity are sufficiently alike, or cause sufficiently similar harms, to trigger this part of the rule. The scope of hybrid rights claims remains uncertain. Burden of persuasion matters only when the court is uncertain, but, as these examples show, the structure of the Supreme Court's rules leave many occasions for uncertainty.
 Page 34       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    The one issue on which the religious claimant always retains the burden of persuasion is burden on religion. Note that in the free exercise context, the claimant need prove only a burden, not a substantial burden. The lower courts have held that where the burdensome rule is not generally applicable, any burden requires compelling justification. Hartmann v. Stone, 68 F.3d 973, 978–79 & nn.3–4 (6th Cir. 1995); Brown v. Borough of Mahaffey, 35 F.3d 846, 849–50 (3d Cir. 1994); Rader v. Johnston, 924 F. Supp. 1540, 1543 n.2 (D. Neb. 1996).

B. Land Use Regulation.

    Section 3(b) enacts prophylactic rules for land use regulation. Section 3(b)(1)(A) provides that land use regulation may not substantially burden religious exercise, except where necessary to prevent substantial and tangible harm. Power to enact this standard without limitation to the scope of the commerce or spending power depends on a hearing record showing ''reason to believe that many of the laws affected by the congressional enactment have a significant likelihood of being unconstitutional.'' City of Boerne v. Flores, 117 S. Ct. 2157, 2170 (1997). Note that the standard is not certainty, but ''reason to believe'' and ''significant likelihood.''

    This is the fourth hearing before this Subcommittee on the subject matter of this bill. The record of these hearings is replete with statistical and anecdotal evidence of likely constitutional violations in land use regulation. More evidence to the same effect is being offered at this hearing. I believe this factual record is ample to support §3(b) as legislation to enforce the Fourteenth Amendment.
 Page 35       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    The hearing record shows that land use regulation is administered through highly individualized determinations not controlled by generally applicable rules. Land use regulation thus falls within the Smith exception for regulatory schemes that permit ''individualized governmental assessment of the reasons for the relevant conduct.'' Church of the Lukumi Babalu Aye, Inc. v. City of Hialeah, 508 U.S. 520, 537 (1993); Employment Div. v. Smith, 494 U.S. 872, 884 (1990). The hearing record also shows that these individualized determinations frequently burden religion and frequently discriminate against religious organizations and especially discriminate against smaller and non-mainstream faiths. Even without the benefit of the Congressional hearing record, some courts have recognized that land use cases can fall within exceptions to the general rule of Employment Division v. Smith. See Korean Buddhist Dae Won Sa Tample v. Sullivan, 953 P.2d 1315, 1344–45 n.31 (Hawaii 1998); First Covenant Church v. City of Seattle, 840 P.2d 174 (Wash. 1992); Keeler v. Mayor of Cumberland, 940 F. Supp. 879 (D. Md. 1996).

    The practice of individualized determinations makes this discrimination extremely difficult to prove in any individual case, but the pattern is clear when Congress examines large numbers of cases through statistical surveys and anecdotal reports from around the country. This record of widespread discrimination and of rules that are not generally applicable shows both the need for, and the constitutional authority to enact, clear general rules that make discrimination more difficult.

    Sections 3(b)(1)(B) and (C) provide that governments may not deny religious assemblies a reasonable location somewhere within each jurisdiction, and that religious assemblies may not be excluded from areas where nonreligious assemblies are permitted. The record of individualized determinations and religious discrimination also supports these provisions, but they are not so dependent on that record. It is unconstitutional to wholly exclude a First Amendment activity from a jurisdiction. Schad v. Borough of Mt. Ephraim, 452 U.S. 61 (1981). Section 3(b)(1)(B) codifies this rule as applied to churches. Discrimination between different categories of speech, and especially discrimination between different viewpoints, already requires strong justification;(see footnote 3) §3(b)(1)(C) codifies this rule as applied to land use regulation that permits secular assemblies while excluding churches.
 Page 36       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Section 3(b)(2) would guarantee a full and fair adjudication of land use claims under subsection (b). Procedural rules before land use authorities may vary widely; any procedure that permits full and fair adjudication of the federal claim would be entitled to full faith and credit in federal court. But if, for example, a zoning board with limited authority refuses to consider the federal claim, does not provide discovery, or refuses to permit introduction of evidence reasonably necessary to resolution of the federal claim, its determination would not be entitled to full faith and credit in federal court. And if in such a case, a state court confines the parties to the record from the zoning board, so that the federal claim still can not be effectively adjudicated, the state court decision would not be entitled to full faith and credit either.

    Full and fair adjudication should include reasonable opportunity to obtain discovery and to develop the facts relevant to the federal claim. Interpretation of this provision should not be controlled by cases deciding whether habeas corpus petitioners had a ''full and fair hearing'' in state court. Interpretation of the habeas corpus standard is often influenced by hostility to convicted criminals seeking multiple rounds of judicial review. Whatever the merits of that hostility, a religious organization seeking to serve existing and potential adherents in a community is not similarly situated.

    Subsection 3(b)(3) provides that equally or more protective state law is not preempted. Zoning law in some states has taken account of the First Amendment needs of churches and synagogues, and to the extent that such law duplicates or supplements RLPA, it is not displaced.

 Page 37       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    Subsection 3(b)(4) provides that §2 shall not apply to land use cases. The more detailed standards of §3(b) control over the more general language of §2. But note that this provision does not say anything about sources of constitutional power. The land use provisions may be upheld in all their applications as an exercise of power to enforce the Fourteenth Amendment; they may also be upheld in many cases as an exercise of the commerce power. There may even be cases of federally assisted land use planning processes in which these provisions would also be an exercise of the spending power. But however many sources of Congressional power support these provisions, the statutory standards to be applied in land use cases come from §3, and not from §2.

V. JUDICIAL RELIEF

A. General Remedies Provisions.

    Section 4 of the bill provides express remedies. Section 4(a) is based on the corresponding provision of RFRA; it authorizes private persons to assert violations of the Act either as a claim or a defense and to obtain appropriate relief. This section should be read against a large body of law on remedies and immunities under civil rights legislation. Appropriate relief includes declaratory judgments, injunctions, and damages, but government officials have qualified immunity from damage claims.

    Section 4(b) provides for attorneys' fees; this is based squarely on RFRA and is essential if the Act is to be enforced.

B. Prisoner Litigation.
 Page 38       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Section 4(c) makes clear that litigation under the bill is subject to the Prison Litigation Reform Act. This provision effectively and adequately responds to concerns about frivolous prisoner litigation. In the first full year under the Prison Litigation Reform Act, federal litigation by state and federal prisoners dropped 31%. Administrative Office of the United States Courts, L. Meacham, Judicial Business of the United States Courts: 1997 Report of the Director 131–32 (Table C–2A). Further reductions may be reasonably expected, as the Act becomes better known; some provisions of the Act, such as the authorization of penalties on prisoners who file three or more frivolous actions, have not yet had much opportunity to work.

    There has been substantial litigation over the constitutionality of some provisions of the Prison Litigation Reform Act, but that litigation does not affect RLPA. The courts of appeals have taken seriously the claim that provisions on existing consent decrees unconstitutionally reopen final judgments. Even so, six out of seven courts of appeals have upheld that part of the Act. Only the Ninth Circuit has struck it down, and only with respect to reopening final judgments.(see footnote 4)

    I have followed this litigation closely for my casebook, Modern American Remedies. I expect the Ninth Circuit to be reversed even in the highly problematic context of reopening final decrees, because the Act addresses only the prospective effect of those decrees. See Plaut v. Spendthrift Farm, Inc., 514 U.S. 211, 232 (1995) (noting Congressional power to ''alter[ ] the prospective effect of injunctions''). But however that difficult issue is resolved, it does not affect RLPA. RLPA does not require that any final judgment be reopened, and the provisions of the Prison Litigation Reform Act most important to RLPA are not the structural reform provisions that have drawn so much litigation, but the provisions that deter frivolous individual claims. I am confident that those provisions are constitutional in all but unusual applications.
 Page 39       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    If further legislative action on prisoner claims is needed, it should follow the approach of the Prison Litigation Reform Act, which addresses prisoner litigation generally. Congress should not exclude prisoners from the substantive protections of RLPA. RFRA did not cause any significant increment to prisoner litigation. The Attorney General of Texas has stated that his office handles about 26,000 active cases at any one time. Of those, 2200 are ''inmate-related, non-capital-punishment cases.'' Of those, sixty were RFRA claims when RFRA applied to the states. Thus, RFRA claims were only 2.7% of the inmate caseload, and only .23% (less than one-quarter of one percent) of the state's total caseload. It is also reasonable to believe that many of these sixty RFRA cases would have been filed anyway, on free exercise, free speech, Eighth Amendment, or other theories. This data is reported in Brief of Amicus Curiae State of Texas 7–8, in City of Boerne v. Flores (No. 95–2074), 117 S.Ct. 2157 (1997).

    Members are well aware that prisoners sometimes file frivolous claims. But they should also be aware that prison authorities sometimes make frivolous rules or commit serious abuses. Examples include Mockaitis v. Harcleroad, 104 F.3d 1522 (9th Cir. 1997), in which jail authorities surreptitiously recorded the sacrament of confession between a prisoner and the Roman Catholic chaplain; Sasnett v. Sullivan, 91 F.3d 1018 (7th Cir. 1996), vacated on other grounds, 117 S.Ct. 2502 (1997), in which a Wisconsin prison rule prevented prisoners from wearing religious jewelry such as crosses, on grounds that Judge Posner found barely rational; and McClellan v. Keen (settled in the District of Colorado in 1994), in which authorities let a prisoner attend Episcopal worship services but forbad him to take communion.

 Page 40       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    RLPA is needed to deal with such abuses to the extent that Congress can reach them. Whether RLPA applies will depend on whether the particular prison system receives federal financial assistance, on whether the prisoner can show a substantial effect on commerce, or on whether the prisoner can show a prima facie violation of the Free Exercise Clause. Probably some prisoner claims will be covered and others will not. But it is important not to exclude those that can be covered.

C. Sovereign Immunity.

    Section 4(d) waives the sovereign immunity of the United States, and overrides the Eleventh Amendment immunity of the states, ''in claims for a violation of the Free Exercise Clause under section 3.'' This waiver and override does not apply to claims under section 2.

    Congress has power to waive the sovereign immunity of the United States whenever it chooses, so there is no doubt about the constitutionality of §4(d)(2). It is a discretionary choice, and not a constitutional requirement, that the bill confines the waiver of sovereign immunity to claims under §3.

    Section 4(d)(1) fully conforms with constitutional limitations on Congressional power to override the Eleventh Amendment immunity of the states. The relevant law is clearly set out in Seminole Tribe v. Florida, 517 U.S. 44 (1996). Seminole Tribe holds that Congress can not override Eleventh Amendment immunity in legislation under the Commerce Clause. It concludes that ''Article I cannot be used to circumvent the constitutional limitations placed upon federal jurisdiction.'' Id. at 73.(see footnote 5)
 Page 41       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    But the Court's opinion twice distinguishes and apparently reaffirms Fitzpatrick v. Bitzer, 427 U.S. 445 (1976). Seminole Tribe, 517 U.S. at 59, 65–66. Fitzpatrick holds that Congress can override Eleventh Amendment immunity in legislation to enforce the Fourteenth Amendment. Then-Justice Rehnquist's opinion for the Court concluded:

But we think that the Eleventh Amendment, and the principle of state sovereignty which it embodies, are necessarily limited by the enforcement provisions of §5 of the Fourteenth Amendment. . . . We think that Congress may, in determining what is ''appropriate legislation'' for the purpose of enforcing the provisions of the Fourteenth Amendment, provide for private suits against States or state officials which are constitutionally impermissible in other contexts.

427 U.S. at 456. Fitzpatrick was a Title VII suit for retroactive pension benefits to be paid by the state of Connecticut, so the holding unambiguously includes suits on statutory claims if the statute was enacted to enforce the Fourteenth Amendment. Accordingly, the override of Eleventh Amendment immunity can include both claims directly under the Free Exercise Clause and claims under §3 of RLPA, which would be enacted to enforce the Free Exercise Clause.

VI. RULES OF CONSTRUCTION.

    The rules of construction in §5 clarify the bill and greatly reduce the risk of misinterpretation.

 Page 42       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    Section 5(a) is based on RFRA. It provides that the Act does not authorize government to burden any religious belief, avoiding any risk that the compelling interest test might be transferred from religious conduct to religious belief. Section 5(b) provides that nothing in the bill creates any basis for regulating or suing any religious organization not acting under color of law. These two subsections serve the bill's central purpose of protecting religious liberty, and avoid any unintended consequence of reducing religious liberty.

    Sections 5(c) and 5(d) keep this bill neutral on all disputed questions about government financial assistance to religious organizations and religious activities. Section 5(c) states neutrality on whether such assistance can or must be provided at all. Section 5(d) states neutrality on the scope of existing authority to regulate private entities as a condition of receiving such aid. Section 5(d)(1) provides that nothing in the bill authorizes additional regulation of such entities; §5(d)(2), perhaps in an excess of caution, provides that existing regulatory authority is not restricted except as provided in the bill. Agencies with authority to regulate the receipt of federal funds retain such authority, but their specific regulations may not substantially burden religious exercise without compelling justification.

    Section 5(e) provides that proof that a religious exercise affects commerce for purposes of this bill does not give rise to an inference or presumption that the religious exercise is subject to any other statute regulating commerce. Different statutes exercise the commerce power to different degrees, and the courts presume that federal statutes do not regulate religious organizations unless Congress manifested the intent to do so. NLRB v. Catholic Bishop, 440 U.S. 490 (1990).

    Section 5(f) states that each provision and application of the bill shall be severable from every other provision and application.
 Page 43       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Section 6 is also a rule of construction, taken directly from RFRA, insuring that this bill does not change results in litigation under the Establishment Clause.

VII. AMENDMENTS TO RELIGIOUS FREEDOM RESTORATION ACT.

    Section 7 of the bill amends RFRA to delete any application to the states and to leave RFRA applicable only to the federal government. Section 7(a)(3) amends the definition of ''religious exercise'' in RFRA to conform it to the RLPA definition, discussed below.

VIII. DEFINITIONS.

    Section 8 contains definitions. Section 8(1) defines ''religious exercise'' to mean ''an act or refusal to act that is substantially motivated by a religious belief, whether or not the act or refusal is compulsory or central to a larger system of religious belief.'' Section 7(a)(3) inserts the same definition into RFRA.

    This definition codifies the intended meaning of RFRA as reflected in its legislative history. The decisions that most thoroughly examined the legislative history and precedent concluded that Congress intended to protect conduct that was religiously motivated, whether or not it was compelled.(see footnote 6)

    The Supreme Court's cases have not distinguished religiously compelled conduct from religiously motivated conduct. The Congressional Reference Service marshalled these opinions for the RFRA hearings, noting that the Court has often referred to protection for religiously motivated conduct. Letter from the American Law Division of the Congressional Research Service to Hon. Stephen J. Solarz (June 11, 1992), in Religious Freedom Restoration Act of 1991: Hearings on H.R. 2797 Before the Subcomm. on Civil and Constitutional Rights of the House Comm. on the Judiciary, 102d Cong., 2d Sess. 131, 131–33 (1992). Since that compilation, justices on both sides of the issue have treated the debate as one over protection for religious motivation, not compulsion.(see footnote 7)
 Page 44       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Congress nowhere expressed any intention to confine the protection of RFRA to practices that were ''central'' to a religion. This concept did not appear either in statutory text or legislative history; it was read into the statute by some courts after RFRA's enactment. Other courts rejected or ignored this misinterpretation; the most extensive opinion concluded that Congress did not intend such a requirement, that pre-RFRA cases did not contain it, and that courts could not resolve disputes about the centrality of religious practices. Muslim v. Frame, 891 F. Supp. 226, 230–31 (E.D. Pa. 1995), aff'd mem., possibly on other grounds, 107 F.3d 7 (1997).

    Insistence on a centrality requirement would insert a time bomb that might destroy the statute, for the Supreme Court has repeatedly stated that courts cannot hold some religious practices to be central and protected, while holding other religious practices noncentral and not protected. Employment Div. v. Smith, 494 U.S. 872, 886–87 (1990); Lyng v. Northwest Indian Cemetery Protective Ass'n, 485 U.S. 439, 457–58 (1985). The Court in Smith unanimously rejected a centrality requirement. 494 U.S. at 886–87 (opinion of the Court); id. at 906–07 (O'Connor, J., concurring); id. at 919 (Blackmun, J., dissenting). The Court's disagreement over whether regulatory exemptions are constitutionally required does not depend on any disagreement about a centrality requirement.

    In the practical application of the substantial burden and compelling interest tests, it is likely to turn out that ''the less central an observance is to the religion in question the less the officials must do'' to avoid burdening it. Mack v. O'Leary, 80 F.3d 1175, 1180 (1996), vacated on other grounds, 118 S.Ct. 36 (1997). The concurring and dissenting opinions in Smith imply a similar view, in the passages cited in the previous paragraph. But this balancing at the margins in individual cases is a very different thing from a threshold requirement of centrality, in which all religious practices are divided into two categories and cases are dismissed as a matter of law if the judge finds, rightly or wrongly, that a practice falls in the noncentral category. Such an either-or threshold requirement greatly multiplies the consequences of the inevitable judicial errors in assessing the importance of religious practices. RLPA properly disavows any such interpretation.
 Page 45       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Section 8(2) cautiously defines the Free Exercise Clause to include both the clause in the First Amendment and the application of that clause to the states through the Fourteenth Amendment.

    Section 8(3) defines government to include both the state and federal governments. But note that for purposes of §2, government includes only state governments. The reason is straightforward. Section 2 adds nothing that will not be in RFRA as amended, and RFRA still applies to the federal government. In re Young, 1998 Westlaw 166642 (8th Cir., Apr. 13, 1998), cert. petition filed (Apr. 27, 1998); EEOC v. Catholic University, 83 F.3d 455, 470–71 (D.C. Cir. 1996). But §3 includes provisions not contained in RFRA, §4 provides remedies that apply to §3, and the rules of construction apply to §3. So all of the bill except §2 properly applies to both the state and federal governments.

IX. OTHER CONSTITUTIONAL OBJECTIONS.

A. The Establishment Clause.

    Justice Stevens suggested that RFRA might violate the Establishment Clause. City of Boerne v. Flores, 117 S.Ct. 2157, 2172 (1997). He got no vote but his own, and his view has no support in the Court's precedents. Government is not obligated to substantially burden the exercise of religion, and government does not establish a religion by leaving it alone. RLPA would not violate the Establishment Clause.

 Page 46       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    The Supreme Court unanimously upheld regulatory exemptions for religious exercise in Corporation of the Presiding Bishop v. Amos, 483 U.S. 327 (1987). There the Court held that Congress may exempt religious institutions from burdensome regulation. The Court so held even with respect to activities that the Court viewed as secular, id. at 330, even though the Court expressly assumed that the exemption was not required by the Free Exercise Clause, id. at 336, and even though the exemption applied only to religious institutions and not to secular ones, id. at 338–39. Amos held that alleviation of government-imposed burdens on religion has a secular purpose, id. at 335–36, and that the religious organization's resulting ability better to advance religious ends is a permitted secular effect, id. at 336–37. Exempting religious practice also avoids entanglement between church and state ''and effectuates a more complete separation of the two.'' Id. at 339. Amos expressly rejected the assumption that exemptions lifting regulatory burdens from the exercise of religion must ''come packaged with benefits to secular entities.'' Id. at 338.

    The Court reaffirmed these principles, after Employment Division v. Smith, in Board of Education v. Grumet:

[T]he Constitution allows the state to accommodate religious needs by alleviating special burdens. Our cases leave no doubt that in commanding neutrality the Religion Clauses do not require the government to be oblivious to impositions that legitimate exercises of state power may place on religious belief and practice.

512 U.S. 687, 705 (1994).

 Page 47       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    The Supreme Court has at times questioned or invalidated exemptions that focus too narrowly on one religious faith or one religious practice, that do not in fact relieve any burden on religious exercise, or that shift the costs of a religious practice to another individual who does not share the faith. Id. at 703; Texas Monthly v. Bullock, 489 U.S. 1 (1989); Estate of Thornton v. Caldor, 472 U.S. 703 (1985). RLPA avoids these constitutional dangers. The bill minimizes the risk of denominational preference by enacting a general standard exempting all religious practices from all substantial and unjustified regulatory burdens; its even-handed generality serves the important Establishment Clause value of neutrality among the vast range of religious practices. By its own terms, the bill does not apply unless there is a substantial burden on the exercise of religion. And if particular proposed applications unfairly shift the costs of a religious practice to another individual, those applications will be avoided by interpreting the compelling interest test or by applying the Establishment Clause to the statute as applied.

    Religion and the exercise of religion should be understood generously for purposes of RLPA, and unconventional beliefs about the great religious questions should be protected. But the Constitution distinguishes religion from other human activities, and it does so for sound reasons. In history that was recent to the American Founders, government regulation of religion had caused problems very different from the regulation of other activities. The worst of those problems are unlikely in America today, and our tradition of religious liberty is surely a large part of the reason. Today the greatest threat to religious liberty is the vast expansion of government regulation. Pervasive regulation regularly interferes with the exercise of religion, sometimes in discriminatory ways, sometimes by the mere existence of so much regulation written from a majoritarian perspective. Many Americans are caught in conflicts between their constitutionally protected religious beliefs and the demands of their government. RLPA would not establish any religion, or religion in general; it would protect the civil liberties of people caught in these conflicts.
 Page 48       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

B. Federalism.

    RLPA is consistent with general principles of federalism that sometimes limit the powers granted to Congress.

    In particular, RLPA would not violate Printz v. United States, 117 S.Ct. 2365 (1997). Printz struck down federal imposition of specific affirmative duties on state officers to implement federal programs. It held that Congress ''cannot compel the States to enact or enforce a federal regulatory program,'' and that it ''cannot circumvent that prohibition by conscripting the State's officers directly.'' Id. at 2384.

    The proposed bill does not impose any specific affirmative duty, implement a federal regulatory program, or conscript state officers. The substantive provisions of the bill are entirely negative; they define one thing that states cannot do, leaving all other options open. The bill thus pre-empts state laws inconsistent with the overriding federal policy of protecting religious liberty in areas constitutionally subject to federal authority.

    The bill operates in the same way as other civil rights laws, which pre-empt state laws that discriminate on the basis of race, sex, and other protected characteristics, and in the same way as other legislation protecting the free flow of commerce from state interference. Congress could itself regulate all transactions affecting interstate commerce, and then exempt burdened religious exercise from its own regulation; it has instead taken the much smaller step of pre-empting state regulation that unnecessarily burdens religious exercise. Cf. New York v. United States, 505 U.S. 144, 167 (1992):
 Page 49       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

Where Congress has power to regulate private activity under the Commerce Clause, we have recognized Congress's power to offer states the choice of regulating that activity according to federal standards or having state law pre-empted by federal regulation.

    RLPA would pre-empt to the minimum extent compatible with the federal policy; it pre-empts the unjustified burden on religious exercise but leaves all other options open. As already noted, §2(d) makes explicit what would be clear in any event—states can pursue any policy they choose, and remove burdens in any way they choose, so long as they do not substantially burden religious exercise without compelling reason.

    Printz distinguishes and leaves unchanged two important pre-emption cases upholding federal statutes in the era of National League of Cities v. Usery, 426 U.S. 833 (1976). In each case, the Printz majority noted that the federal law ''merely made compliance with federal standards a precondition to continued state regulation in an otherwise pre-empted field.'' 117 S.Ct. at 2380.

    The first of these cases was Hodel v. Virginia Surface Mining & Reclamation Ass'n, Inc., 452 U.S. 264 (1981), which upheld a federal statute that required states either to affirmatively implement a specific federal regulatory program or turn the field over to direct federal regulation. The Court said that ''nothing'' in National League of Cities ''shields the States from pre-emptive federal regulation of private activities affecting interstate commerce.'' Id. at 291. Hodel is reaffirmed not only in Printz, but also in New York v. United States, 505 U.S. 144, 161 (1992).
 Page 50       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    The Court reached similar conclusions in Federal Energy Regulatory Comm'n v. Mississippi, 456 U.S. 742 (1982) (the FERC case). The statute there went further, and required the state to ''consider'' implementing an affirmative federal policy. But the state was not required to adopt the policy, and law's provisions ''simply condition continued state involvement in a pre-emptible area on the consideration of federal proposals.'' Id. at 765.

    In Hodel, the Court commented that ''Congress could constitutionally have enacted a statute prohibiting any state regulation of surface coal mining.'' Id. at 290. RLPA would not go nearly so far. It would prohibit only some state regulation of religious exercise—regulation that falls within the reach of spending or commerce powers, that substantially burdens religious exercise, and that cannot be justified by a compelling interest.

    Hodel and FERC also went much further than RLPA in another way, because they required states either to implement or consider specific and affirmative federal policies or cede the field to federal regulation. RLPA imposes no specific policies, but only the general limitation that whatever policies they pursue, states can not substantially burden religious exercise without compelling reason.

    Some provisions of the statutes in Hodel and FERC were directed expressly to the states and, in a sense, applied only to the states. Only the state agency could implement or consider the federal policy. But this did not render the statutes invalid for singling out the states. Congress was pursuing a policy for the appropriate regulation of private conduct, and it required the states to conform to that policy or to vacate the field. This is the classic work of federal pre-emption.
 Page 51       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    If RLPA seems in any way odd, it is because the federal policy with respect to the private sector is generally one of deregulation, not regulation. The Congressional policy is that religious exercise not be substantially burdened without compelling reason. Congress has no more affirmative or more specific regulatory policy for religion to substitute for the pre-empted regulation. But that is not unique either. As Professor Thomas Berg points out in a forthcoming article, the statutes deregulating the transportation industries broadly pre-empted state regulation and substituted only minimal federal regulation in its place. He cites the Staggers Rail Act of 1980, 40 U.S.C. §10505 (1994), and the Airline Deregulation Act of 1978, 49 U.S.C. §41701 et seq. (1994).

    It is instructive to compare the pre-emption provision of the Airline Deregulation Act with the central provision of RLPA:

Table 1

    There is no difference in structure or in principle between these two provisions. Both on their face regulate state laws and only state laws. Both in their operation pre-empt state laws that are inconsistent with a federal policy of deregulation. The Airline Deregulation Act provision was broadly construed, without constitutional challenge, in Morales v. Trans World Airlines, Inc., 504 U.S. 374 (1992). Nothing in either Printz or the National League of Cities line of cases casts doubt on federal power to pre-empt state regulation inconsistent with federal policy in areas where Congress could regulate directly if it chose. That is all the Religious Liberty Protection Act would do.

 Page 52       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
X. CONCLUSION.

    This bill is needed for the reasons set forth by other witnesses and in earlier hearings. The bill's opponents seem to be few in number, but they are able and creative; they can think of many arguments. In this testimony, I have tried to anticipate those arguments.

    No one can predict how the Supreme Court might change the law in the future. But Congress should not be intimidated into not exercising powers that have been established for decades because of the risk that the law might change in the future. The bill is clearly within Congressional power under existing law, and I urge its enactment.

    Mr. CANADY. Professor Berg.

STATEMENT OF THOMAS C. BERG, PROFESSOR, CUMBERLAND LAW SCHOOL, SAMFORD UNIVERSITY

    Mr. BERG. Thank you, Mr. Chairman. I appreciate the opportunity to come today and testify about the religious liberty protection bill.

    I have two themes to what I want to say today. First is that this bill is drafted with several components of congressional power, and there is a good reason for that. One of the moral advantages of the Religious Freedom Restoration Act was in its breadth of coverage; that it reached all claims of religious exercise brought by people of all faiths, majority faiths, minority faiths, popular ones, unpopular ones. It assured equal religious liberty for people of different faiths as opposed to a case-by-case kind of accommodation where the squeaky wheel gets the grease or the more powerful interest is accommodated over others.
 Page 53       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Now, Congress cannot reach the same breadth of religious practices that it did under RFRA because of the Court's ruling in the Boerne case. It must rely on more discrete powers like the more limited Fourteenth Amendment powers that remain, the Spending Clause and the Commerce Power. But there still remains an important advantage, moral advantage, in general—in legislation that is as general as possible and protects as many religious faiths and claims as is possible. And that is a reason for Congress to try to exercise all of the powers that it has available to it and to think very carefully before it considers foregoing any reliance on any of these powers.

    The second theme is don't make the perfect the enemy of the good. We can't have a statute that is quite as broad as RFRA was because of Boerne, but that shouldn't blind us to what this bill can actually accomplish.

    Now I want to talk a little bit about constitutional power under the Spending Clause and the Commerce Clause and echo quite a bit of what Professor Laycock said. Under the spending power, the constitutional basis for the statute is extremely strong. There is—well, as Professor Laycock said, the statute tracks the established language in Title VI and other programs, other civil rights laws, involving federally—Federal funding of State programs.

    There is a strong Federal interest in assuring that beneficiaries of those programs do not have their religious freedom burdened, and particularly in assuring that they do not have to drop out of the program and lose the benefits of it because of conflicts with their religious belief. It is perfectly reasonable for Congress to conclude that that happens.
 Page 54       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Just one example, I think, would be it is perfectly reasonable to think that a number—a number of parents who have left the public schools have done so because of conflicts between public school regulations and their religious beliefs. There are reported cases on those kinds of conflicts, and I think it is something that happens.

    Now, the Spending Power would have important effects, as the public school cases show. In public schools alone there have been plenty of cases of religious freedom conflicting with school regulations over the years; objections to curriculum to force—for children being forced to be exposed to curriculums that violate their religious beliefs; questions about whether student religious groups can have as a criterion that their leaders be members of the faith. That has been an issue that religious groups have had to litigate; questions about whether students can wear nondangerous religious garb or jewelry in the schools. All of those cases would be within the coverage of the bill. The religious believer might not win in every case, but the Spending Clause would have important effects.

    To reiterate the strength of the spending power basis constitutionally, the governing law on this is South Dakota v. Dole, written by Chief Justice Rehnquist and joined by Justice Scalia, which said that as long as there is a reasonable relation between the purpose of the expenditure and the condition, that the condition is constitutional.

    I think even if the Court were to tighten up on that a little bit, this provision falls well within the Spending Power because of the Federal interests that I described.

    Now, on the commerce power, I want to say something briefly about the nature of this statute. It may seem in some ways inappropriate to rely on the commerce power to protect a fundamental civil right such as religious freedom, but before we start thinking along those lines, we should remember that Congress has done that many, many times, and perhaps the major precedent here is the Civil Rights Act of 1964, which protected the human right of equality and nondiscrimination based on a rationale that discrimination affected interstate commerce.
 Page 55       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    On the constitutional power under the Commerce Clause, religious entities do affect commerce. Congress should make careful and detailed findings—detailed findings on that. There will be evidence to support that. But the whole range of Federal regulation, based on the Commerce Clause, has typically been applied to religious institutions, based on the premise that they affect commerce. When religious institutions have been free from the Fair Labor Standards Act or the National Labor Relations Board jurisdiction or other commerce statutes, Title VII, it has not been because courts have ever held that they fall outside the scope of commerce. It has been because of religious freedom concerns or because the statute was drafted in a way that did not reach them, did not reach to the full scope of the commerce power.

    It seems to me that if religious entities can be regulated under the Commerce Clause, subject to First Amendment or other kinds of exemptions, but if they can be within the scope of regulation under the Commerce Clause, then Congress certainly has the power to exempt them from State regulation under the Commerce Clause as well. That seems only to follow as a matter of fairness.

    In some cases, the religious entity in itself may not affect interstate commerce in an individual case, but where the institution is engaged in some kind of commercial activity, the law is clear. Even under United States v. Lopez, that individual instances can be aggregated for the purpose of calculating the effect on interstate commerce, Lopez says that clearly. Numerous court of appeals decisions after Lopez have reaffirmed that the aggregation theory remains viable where there is some commercial component to the activity.

 Page 56       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    In the case of religious entities, employment is a commercial activity. Religious entities buy and sell materials in order to serve their parishioners or their beneficiaries or the general public. They engage in a number of different kinds of activities that would fall within the notion of commercial.

    That applies to small entities as well, not just large entities that individually are involved in interstate commerce. Because of the aggregation theory, the valid aggregation theory, small entities can be covered as well.

    Individual cases will sometimes be covered when the individual is engaged in commercial activity and the religious conflict comes up in that case, or when there is some kind of commercial connection. As Professor Laycock indicated, the bill won't cover the case unless some kind of connection to interstate commerce can be made.

    Finally, I want to say something about the United States v. Printz decision, the State sovereignty question, and to echo Professor Laycock's point on that. There is a tremendous difference between the affirmative mandate to State officials that was struck down in the Brady bill case, Printz, and the simple displacing of State laws that happens—that would happen under a religious liberty bill, displacing of State laws for the purpose of deregulating, leaving unregulated, private activity, religious activity by private individuals and groups. In most cases—well, go back. The courts said that preemption, the displacing of State laws by preemption, even after Printz clearly remains within Congress' power. And in most cases, Congress replaces the State law with its own scheme of regulation, and that is why this case may seem a little different from other preemption cases, but it is not.
 Page 57       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    There are examples of deregulatory preemption. The deregulation of the trucking industry, Congress deregulated the trucking industry and preempted State laws that would continue to regulate it. The same thing, as Professor Laycock indicated, with the airline industry, and you should read his testimony to note the striking parallels between the provision in the Airline Deregulation Act and the provision of the religious liberty bill.

    I will stop there and thank you for the opportunity.

    Mr. CANADY. Thank you, Professor Berg.

    [The prepared statement of Mr. Berg follows:]

PREPARED STATEMENT OF THOMAS C. BERG, PROFESSOR, CUMBERLAND LAW SCHOOL, SAMFORD UNIVERSITY

    I appreciate the opportunity to appear today and give testimony concerning the Religious Liberty Protection Act of 1998 (RLPA). I am friendly toward this bill, but I am not particularly an insider on it; I saw and commented on one early version but have had no further involvement in the drafting. I am testifying, of course, in my personal capacity and not as a representative of my institutions, Cumberland Law School or Samford University.

    My testimony has two purposes, although they overlap. One purpose is to address some questions that have been raised concerning the constitutionality of various provisions of RLPA, or the maximum scope that those provisions could have and still be constitutional. The second purpose is to address some criticisms of the bill, primarily those raised by a few conservative organizations and individuals. Several of those criticisms are on constitutional grounds, hence the overlap. But before I discuss constitutional issues in detail, I want to say a few words about the value of legislation like RLPA and the superiority of such legislation to the alternatives.
 Page 58       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

A. THE VALUE OF GENERAL RELIGIOUS FREEDOM LEGISLATION

    The premise of this testimony, and of RLPA itself, is that the proper scope of religious freedom requires that sometimes religiously motivated conduct be protected against generally applicable laws—not just against laws that single out religious conduct for prohibition. To the founding generation, religious conscience was worth protecting because it involved duties to a higher power, duties that in James Madison's words were ''precedent, both in order of time and degree of obligation, to the claims of Civil Society.''(see footnote 8) Religious duties also tend, as a class, to be especially deeply felt and to provoke especially strong reaction when the believer is forced to violate them. These harms—the violation of deeply felt duties to a higher power—affect religious believers or groups whenever their religious practices are prohibited by law, whether or not the law applies to a host of other people or not. Particularly in this day of pervasive government regulation, religious conduct will be highly restricted if it is subject to every law that applies to the broader society.

    We continue to return here because this vision of religious freedom is not fully protected under existing law. The Supreme Court held in Employment Division v. Smith(see footnote 9) that the Free Exercise Clause usually is not violated by the application of a ''neutral and generally applicable'' law to prohibit religious conduct. This general rule has a number of possible limits and exceptions, which can be and have been used to protect religious freedom in particular circumstances. But litigation under those exceptions is complex and uncertain and still may produce insufficient scope for religious freedom in a highly regulated society.

 Page 59       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    For these reasons, Congress in 1993 passed the Religious Freedom Restoration Act (RFRA), which provided that even generally applicable federal and state laws could not impose ''substantial'' burdens on religious exercise unless they were supported by strong governmental interests. But the Supreme Court last year in City of Boerne v. Flores(see footnote 10) struck down RFRA as applied to state and local laws, holding that the statute exceeded Congress's Fourteenth Amendment power to enforce constitutional rights against states. The Court said that the Fourteenth Amendment power was limited to enforcing the Court's interpretation of the Free Exercise Clause. Since the largest number of restrictions on religious practice come from generally applicable laws at the state and local levels, Boerne returned religious freedom to the very uncertain state that existed before RFRA.

    There are important reasons for Congress to try again to pass religious freedom legislation that shares some of the qualities of RFRA. It is important to protect religious exercise from generally applicable laws. Moreover, it is important to do so in a consistent, across-the-board fashion. RFRA, which protected all claims of religious exercise under the same standard, reflected a moral, constitutional, and practical insight: that religious freedom protection should be the same for all groups. In the words of the Coalition for the Free Exercise of Religion, RFRA was meant ''to allow[] any faith, no matter how small, unpopular or politically ineffectual, to press its claims before a neutral arbiter under an objective and religiously neutral standard. The consideration and adjudication of [such] claims facilitates judicial review for fairness and minimizes favoritism.''(see footnote 11)

    The Religious Liberty Protection Act seeks to provide as broad a coverage of religious freedom claims as is possible after the Boerne decision, by relying on a variety of enumerated powers including but not limited to the Fourteenth Amendment enforcement power. As members of Congress discuss the several components of the legislation, I urge them to remember that it is an important goal to try to cover as wide a range of religious practices as is possible.
 Page 60       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    The value of general religious freedom legislation is shown by the fact that RFRA itself accomplished some important results during a very short time.(see footnote 12) Just in its application to state laws, the statute had preserved the confidentiality of Catholic confessions from invasion by prosecutors,(see footnote 13) enabled soup kitchens and homeless shelters to overcome or limit seriously burdensome zoning regulations,(see footnote 14) and permitted Amish buggy drivers, Sikh children, and prisoners of various faiths to follow religious practices in ways not causing danger to others.(see footnote 15)

    It is true that in recent years, religious believers and institutions have sometimes managed to protect themselves within the framework of Employment Division v. Smith, by arguing that the law burdening them was not generally applicable, that it was applied in a discriminatory fashion, or that it implicated some ''hybrid'' of another constitutional interest with religious exercise. But it would not be wise to rely solely on litigation under Smith. Discriminatory intent and discriminatory application of law are difficult to prove. There is no guarantee that the Supreme Court will end up maintaining the ''hybrid''-rights category of analysis or that it will accept all of the broad assertions of hybrid rights, especially expressive rights, that have succeeded in some lower court decisions. In any event, RLPA would add an explicit form of protection to the claims that religious believers and institutions can raise. Lawyers representing churches and believers continue to report that while RFRA was in effect, it improved their position in negotiating with state and local government officials.

 Page 61       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    Some critics of RLPA, especially from the conservative side, acknowledge the need to protect religious freedom from generally applicable laws but claim that there are better ways to do so. This is the position of the recent memorandum from the Home School Legal Defense Association (HSLDA), the only written arguments of this kind of which I am aware. But the alternatives HSLDA suggests are simply not viable; dropping RLPA and pursuing them would truly make the perfect the enemy of the good.

    Two of the alternatives HSLDA suggests cannot, with all respect, be taken seriously: ''passing a Congressional resolution stating that RFRA is constitutional'' and ''re-enacting RFRA without changes as a demonstration to the Supreme Court that Congress believes RFRA to be constitutional.''(see footnote 16) These measures would either have no legal force or else would be struck down immediately in litigation, most likely with monetary sanctions imposed on the religious believers who raised the ''reenacted'' RFRA as a claim. There is no point in Congress merely thumbing its nose at the Court or precipitating a direct constitutional clash by reenacting a statute struck down a year ago.

    The other two suggested options—state RFRA-type statutes or a federal constitutional amendments—are more serious, but those who have given the most thought to protecting religious freedom after Boerne have concluded that they are not adequate in themselves. The push for state constitutional amendments and RFRA-type statutes, of course, is vigorously underway and is already yielding fruits. But the state-by-state process moves very slowly, and its results are practically guaranteed to be uneven. Various states have proposed to immunize prisoner regulations, anti-discrimination laws, and other kinds of laws from having to satisfy heightened scrutiny. Federal action would provide an important supplement to the patchwork of state rules.
 Page 62       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    That leaves a federal constitutional amendment. I am no expert on politics, but those who are and are closest to the religious freedom efforts have concluded unanimously that an amendment is not a viable option. Their reasons seem compelling. The process is long and arduous, and nothing would be accomplished unless the required three-fourths of the states ratified the amendment. Interest groups that oppose religious freedom in particular circumstances—groups from prison wardens to the architectural preservation lobby to public educators to animal rights activists—could force exceptions to be written into the amendment at the front end. More likely and more dangerously, they could defeat it entirely at the back end by blocking passage in just a few states. The experience could be similar to that of the Equal Rights Amendment, which shot out of the starting gate in 1972 but ran into insurmountable barriers in getting the last three states necessary to ratify. The amendment process would also tend to sweep in other issues in the contentious area of church and state, such as prayers in public schools and financial aid to religious schools. Congress knows from very recent experience that disputes over those matters would divide religious freedom advocates and doom any such amendment.

    Given the value of religious freedom legislation, there would have to be strong reasons to justify opposing it. The criticisms I have seen, whether they are of policy or of constitutionality, do not seem to me to make a sufficient case against RLPA. I am going to address the criticisms by first discussing two of the major sources of power on which RLPA would rely—the Spending and Commerce powers—and then turn to other matters.

B. SPENDING POWER COMPONENT

    Section 2(a)(1) of RLPA would apply heightened scrutiny to substantial burdens on religious exercise imposed ''in a program or activity, operated by a government, that receives Federal financial assistance.'' The basis for this authority is Congress's power to tax and spend for the general welfare,(see footnote 17) under which Congress can set conditions on the use of its expenditures. The provision is modeled on the various anti-discrimination laws, which prohibit discrimination based on race, sex, handicap, or age in any program or activity receiving federal funds.(see footnote 18) The purpose of the provision is to ensure that federal funds are not used to support burdens on the religious practice of beneficiaries, and that beneficiaries are not forced to withdraw from federally funded programs, and forego the programs' advantages, because the programs impose burdens on their faith. For example, the federal government offers funding to most public school districts in order to help them provide a better education. When school districts impose unnecessary burdens on the religious conscience of parents and students—whether through forcing students to read objectionable materials or exposing them to unnecessary or excessive sex education programs(see footnote 19)—those parents may well move their children to private schools, which would frustrate the federal purpose of aiding their education. RLPA might not require accommodations in all these cases, but it would require the school to prove that no accommodation can be made.
 Page 63       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    These purposes easily satisfy the current Spending Power test, set forth in South Dakota v. Dole.(see footnote 20) There the Court upheld Congress's power to condition federal highway funds on a state's adopting a 21-year-old minimum drinking age. The condition concerning teenage drinking, the Court said, bore a reasonable relation to highway construction because of concerns for highway safety. If such a loose connection was sufficient in Dole, certainly there is a sufficient interest in preventing federally subsidized programs from burdening or driving away their beneficiaries because of impositions on their faith.(see footnote 21)

    The HSLDA's objection to the Spending Power component of RLPA is not that it is inappropriate, but that it ''will not often be of assistance to religious believers'' because ''very few free exercise cases come up in the context of federally funded programs.''(see footnote 22) That is simply false. Most public school districts will be covered, and they have given rise to a number of religious freedom disputes—from the curriculum and sex education disputes mentioned above, to questions about whether student religious groups may limit their leadership or membership to adherents of their faith,(see footnote 23) whether students may wear religious items mandated by their faith,(see footnote 24) and whether schools may disregard the educational level and achievements of religiously home-schooled students when they enter the public system.(see footnote 25) When one adds in public universities, state welfare programs, and other state activities receiving federal funding, the number of likely religious freedom interests covered by RLPA is far from few.

 Page 64       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
For some unexplained reason, the HSLDA memorandum includes public school students on its list of persons who would have no protection under RLPA. HSLDA Mem. at 6.

C. COMMERCE POWER COMPONENT

    Section 2(a)(2) of RLPA would apply heightened scrutiny to burdens on religious exercise ''in or affecting commerce with foreign nations, among the several States, or with the Indian tribes.'' The basic theory of congressional power here is that, at least in some instances, religious believers and institutions are actors in commerce, buying or selling goods or services or employing people, and that government restriction of their activity may thereby reduce or distort commerce as well as religious exercise. This component of the bill has attracted the most criticism from the conservative side, and it also raises the most complicated constitutional issues. I would like to address several points concerning it.

1. Reliance on a Commercial Rationale

    Some of the critics' objections to the Commerce Power component of RLPA are not on constitutional grounds, but on what might be called moral, rhetorical, or even theological grounds. They argue that a ''reduction of faith and religious practice to commerce'' is demeaning, ''sacrilegious'' and ''at the very least silly.''(see footnote 26) ''Never before in our Nation's history,'' they cry, ''has a fundamental right been reduced to a level of a commercial transaction.''(see footnote 27) They also complain that the commercial rationale will distract attention from the real task of restoring religious freedom by new Fourteenth Amendment legislation or by a constitutional amendment.(see footnote 28)
 Page 65       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    These critics have a very short memory. The landmark Civil Rights Act of 1964 did precisely what RLPA does: protect a fundamental human right, in that case equality and nondiscrimination, using the Commerce Power as the means to that end. And almost exactly the same warnings and criticisms were made at the time. But the fact that Congress prohibited discrimination in employment and public accommodations based on their effect on commerce and interstate travel has scarcely deprived the Civil Rights Act of its moral force or of its status in American law.

    Congress faced a similar constitutional problem in 1964 with civil rights that it faces today with religious freedom. Although the Fourteenth Amendment was the constitutional provision that spoke directly to the ideal of racial equality that motivated the Act, Congress thought it was foreclosed from relying on the Amendment (at least solely on it) because of the Court's interpretations. There, the Court had held decades earlier that a public accommodations law could not rest on the Fourteenth Amendment because the law reached beyond state action to private businesses.(see footnote 29) Here, although the Fourteenth Amendment speaks most directly to religious freedom against state laws, Congress is foreclosed from broadly protecting religious freedom under the Amendment because of Boerne.

    The Commerce Power rationale for the Civil Rights bill prompted criticisms—even from some who supported the bill's goals—that are echoed by the criticisms today of RLPA. One senator complained that ''[the] dignity of the individual should not be placed on lesser grounds such as the [commerce clause]'';(see footnote 30) another argued that discrimination was wrong because of ''the dignity of man, not because it impedes our [commerce],'' and complained that relying on the Commerce Power to avoid the Fourteenth Amendment difficulties was ''too careful, cagey, and cautious.''(see footnote 31)
 Page 66       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    There is one difference between the two situations that points in RLPA's favor. In 1964 some observers dismissed the Commerce Power basis for the civil rights law partly because they thought a viable basis could be developed under the Fourteenth Amendment: the Court's narrow state action decision was very old and more recent decisions had expanded that concept.(see footnote 32) But today we are certain that the Court will not let Congress legislate strict scrutiny for religious exercise claims under the Fourteenth Amendment; Boerne said so only a year ago. The prospect of forcing the Court down by reenacting RFRA is laughable, as I have said. Outside of the Spending Power and the rather limited Fourteenth Amendment option, the Commerce Power is the only basis for legislating to protect religious exercise from generally applicable laws.

    The parallels between the Civil Rights Act and RLPA should, I think, lead Congress not to be scared off too quickly by cries like ''Worship is not commerce!'' The Civil Rights Act has not lost its moral force or importance just because it used the fact that discrimination affects commerce as a means to support congressional power. Nor is there a lack of moral force in the federal statutes prohibiting child labor, toxic waste dumping, terrorism, arson against businesses, or a host of other activities that are condemned on primarily moral rather than commercial grounds—but where the federal prohibition rests on the Commerce Power.

2. The Constitutionally Permissible Scope of Protection

    There have also been questions raised concerning the power of Congress to protect religious exercise based on its effect on interstate commerce. Strictly speaking, there can be no constitutional difficulty with the statute's text; it extends protection only to religious exercise ''in or affecting [interstate] commerce,'' a phrase intended to reach as far as, but only as far as, the Commerce Power permits. (Congress might wish to consider stating explicitly(see footnote 33) that the provision is meant to extend to the limits of the Commerce Power.) The provision is thus constitutional by definition. It contains what United States v. Lopez,(see footnote 34) the Court's recent Commerce Power decision, requires: a ''jurisdictional element which would ensure, through case-by-case inquiry, that the [activity] in question affects interstate commerce.''(see footnote 35) The real question, then, is what religious activity can be held to affect interstate commerce under the Supreme Court's decisions. My judgment is that the Commerce Power component could have some significant effects, although its reach would be limited.
 Page 67       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Religious activity and governmental regulation of it affect interstate commerce because religious entities are themselves actors in commerce. Worship is not commerce, but many of the entities that engage in it also engage in commerce. Churches, schools, social service agencies, and other religious entities purchase and produce goods and services and employ people commerce, and to a large degree: the total expenditure by religious organizations is probably more than $100 billion a year, no doubt much of it the purchase of goods and services that move in interstate commerce.(see footnote 36) Regulation of their activities affects how they engage in commerce. When labor laws regulate a religious entity's employment practices—for examples, requiring a school to accept unionization of its teachers, or to pay unemployment benefits to employees discharged for conduct the school regards as sinful—the entity may hire fewer employees, or in a different pattern, than if it were not regulated. If a Roman Catholic hospital loses its obstetrics accreditation because it refuses to teach abortion techniques, the obstetrics services and the teaching program will shift to another hospital.

    The fact that any single instance of restricted economic activity does not affect interstate commerce will not matter. Even in Lopez, which signaled the resurrection of judicial limits on the Commerce Power, the Court continued to allow Congress to regulate ''economic activity that might, through repetition elsewhere, substantially affect any sort of interstate commerce.''(see footnote 37) A host of appeals decisions since Lopez have confirmed that Congress can reach local activity that in the ''aggregate'' would affect interstate commerce, at least if the activity is in some way economic or has a commercial connection.(see footnote 38) I do urge Congress to make as detailed findings as possible concerning the effect on commerce from different kinds of religious activity and from the regulation of them. I hope that the testimony presented at these hearings will be a significant step toward such findings.
 Page 68       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Lopez, of course, indicates that the Court is beginning once again to set limits on the Commerce Power, and it is hard to know just how far that limiting process will go. But we can sketch some likely lines of reasoning and how they would affect the reach of RLPA.

    First, I think it is almost certain that the Court will continue to regard some forms of activity as inherently economic or connected to commerce, and thus more easily subject to congressional action. The most important of these are employment practices—unionization, payment of wages and benefits, selection of employees, and so forth. The Court will continue to regard these as within the scope of commerce, even for fairly small or local entities, based on an aggregation theory. Thus it seems likely that RLPA would cover most of the instances where state labor laws—collective bargaining laws, anti-discrimination laws, unemployment benefits laws—would require religious institutions to violate their conscience or compromise their mission. The proposition that religious entities affect commerce is the premise for subjecting them to various federal labor laws, including ERISA, the Fair Labor Standards Act, the National Labor Relations Act, Title VII of the Civil Rights Act, and others. It cannot be that religious entities are engaged in commerce when Congress regulates them, but not when Congress decides to exempt them from regulation.

    The HSLDA attack on the bill is misleading when it suggests that the Court may be moving toward a very strict reading of the Commerce Power that would encompass only ''the power to regulate railroads, highways, and other means of transporting goods from state to state.''(see footnote 39) HSLDA seems to imply that encouraging such a reading is worthwhile, although it would render RLPA ineffective, because it would enable religious entities to avoid federal regulation by arguing that they do not affect commerce. I see little prospect for such a change. The Court is most unlikely to make a serious assault on the Civil Rights Act and other labor laws premised on aggregate activity under the Commerce Power.
 Page 69       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    The notion that religious entities could avoid federal regulation by arguing that they are outside commerce is a longshot, even after Lopez; it is not worth foregoing the protection against state regulation offered by RLPA. I have not found one decision in which a religious entity avoided federal regulation by showing it fell outside the Commerce Power; there are numerous decisions finding religious entities to be within commerce, even for their non-profit, spiritual activities.(see footnote 40) Where religious entities have escaped federal statutory coverage, it is because they have been carved out as an exception from full coverage of activities affecting commerce—sometimes because of First Amendment concerns,(see footnote 41) sometimes as a matter of statutory or administrative decision.(see footnote 42) Nothing in RLPA would interfere with such statutory or administrative exceptions; under section 5(e), proof that an entity affects commerce under RLPA ''does not give rise to any inference or presumption that the religious exercise is subject to any other law regulating commerce.''

    HSLDA is wrong, I believe, when it suggests that the protections of the Commerce Power component would probably apply only to large religious institutions and not to small entities such as ''small churches,'' ''day care centers,'' ''Christian landlords,'' or businesses owned by the religiously devout.(see footnote 43) The employment and other commercially-related practices of small religious entities have an effect on commerce in the aggregate. As I have discussed, the law has clearly exposed these small entities to federal regulation under the Commerce Power; it would make no sense to say that they cannot be protected from state restriction under that same power.

    A closer question is presented by forms of religious activity that have a less fully commercial nature but have some connections to commerce. For example, when prison rules forbid the distribution of religious literature or jewelry to inmates, the main restricted religious activity, the reading of literature or the wearing of jewelry, has little of a commercial nature (just as the Court in Lopez held that gun possession had little commercial nature). But another, connected religious activity, the production and distribution of religious literature or jewelry, has commercial element and may be affected on a large or interstate scale—especially if, for example, the restrictive policy is adopted by an entire state prison system. My guess is that such questions will have to be resolved on a case-by-case basis.
 Page 70       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Most of the forms of religiously significant activity that are likely to be deemed economic—employment, the provision of medical or social services or instruction, the purchase of materials, the making of contracts—are engaged in by religious institutions such as churches, schools, or social service agencies. The commerce rationale will not apply as often to individual religious exercise, which usually does not have a direct commercial element. Some conflicts between individual religious exercise and the laws arise out of individuals' commercial activity: for example, cases where landlords assert conscientious objections to being forced by law to accept unmarried cohabiting couples as tenants.(see footnote 44) But many individual cases do not involve commercial activity, including some of the most compelling cases for protecting individual religious conscience. That cost simply follows from the fact that Congress's power under the Commerce Clause is limited.

    HSLDA views these limits on the Commerce Power as a reason to scrap RLPA altogether. I disagree; they are not even sufficient reason to scrap the Commerce Power component alone. The protection of religious institutions' autonomy in matters like employment is an important benefit in itself. Many of the more compelling cases for religious accommodations involve the right of institutions to determine their mission, how it will be carried out, and by whom. And in areas like employment, small entities are likely to be protected as well as large ones. Finally, the limits on the Commerce Power component are surely not a good reason to reject the entire statute. As the examples about coverage of public schools show, many of the impositions on religious freedom that are beyond the Commerce Power can be addressed by the components of RLPA based on the Spending and the Fourteenth Amendment Enforcement powers.

3. Tenth Amendment Issues
 Page 71       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Another constitutional issue that has been raised is whether a Commerce Power component would violate Tenth Amendment limits on congressional power. In two recent decisions, United States v. Printz and New York v. United States, the Court has held that Congress is prohibited from ''compel[ling] the States to implement, by legislation or executive action, federal regulatory programs.''(see footnote 45) Printz struck down the Brady Act's requirement that sheriffs check the background of gun purchasers in their county; New York struck down a provision that required each state to develop a satisfactory plan for disposing of radioactive waste or else ''take title'' to the waste. It has been suggested that RLPA's Commerce Power component likewise directly orders states to pursue a certain policy toward religious exercise (namely, refraining from burdening it except for a compelling governmental interest).(see footnote 46) Some of the language in those decisions would provide support for such an argument.

These holdings, it should be noted, do not apply to the Spending Power; Congress may condition funds to a state or its agency on the condition that it follow federal directives in using them. New York, 505 U.S. at 173; Printz, 117 S. Ct. at 2376.

    But the protection of religious freedom from state laws under RLPA presents a very different situation from the congressional ''commandeering'' of state officials struck down in Printz and New York. The key difference lies in the fact that RLPA does not put an affirmative mandate on state and local governments to carry out a federal program: rather, RLPA simply displaces state and local laws to the extent necessary to protect the activity of private religious individuals and organizations. Therefore, the Commerce Power rule of RLPA is more analogous to legislation preempting state and local laws, which is of course common under the Commerce Power.
 Page 72       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Reading Printz, New York and Lopez to forbid Congress from displacing state laws would create serious difficulties with the power of preemption. Any preemption clause in a federal statute is in effect a direct regulation of state and local lawmaking. If Printz and New York (or even Lopez) mean that Congress cannot directly target state law in the sense of displacing it, then those decisions will cast doubt on the preemption power, for every preemption provision singles out state laws for displacement. That would fly in the face of the New York Court's assurance that the preemption power is not affected.

    It is crucial to emphasize that the Commerce Power component of RLPA simply displaces state law (except where a compelling interest is present); it does not mandate any federal regulation or program. RLPA can be satisfied in any number of ways, indeed by any way that removes the burden on religious exercise. The bill provides that ''[a] government may eliminate the substantial burden on religious exercise by changing the policy that results in the burden, by retaining the policy and exempting the religious exercise from that policy, or by any means that eliminates the burden.''(see footnote 47) Thus there is simply no argument that RLPA ''commandeers'' the states or ''compel[s them] to enact or administer a federal regulatory program.'' This leaves the government with considerable flexibility, and it makes possible negotiations between religious believers and the government that often produce a solution acceptable to both. For example, when a public high school basketball league forbade an Orthodox Jewish student to wear a yarmulke while playing because the cap might fall off and trip other players, the federal court (applying the pre-Smith balancing test that RLPA would restore) suggested that a more secure form of headgear might satisfy the state's safety concerns while allowing the student to fulfill his religious duty. The parties eventually settled on similar terms.(see footnote 48)
 Page 73       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    In many preemption situations, Congress replaces the displaced state law with a scheme of federal regulation; Justice O'Connor referred to this when she spoke of Congress ''regulat[ing] interstate commerce directly.''(see footnote 49) But in some federal statutes, the regulatory scheme that Congress imposes is one of deregulation. Congress intends to increase the freedom of private actors and in order to do so, forbids the application of state or local laws to the deregulated conduct. Congress replaces state law with no legal restrictions at all in some instances, and at most minimal and flexible ones. The preemption provision is, of course, crucial to the deregulatory goal, but it is not replaced with any significant federal regulation. Recent examples include the statutes deregulating airlines rates(see footnote 50) and railroad and trucking industry operations.(see footnote 51) A few terms ago, the Court broadly interpreted the preemption provision in the Airline Deregulation Act to forbid state attorneys general from bringing enforcement proceedings against airline rate advertisements under generally applicable state laws forbidding false advertising.(see footnote 52)

    The Commerce Power component of RLPA can be seen as a kind of deregulatory statute preempting state laws that impede on the freedom Congress wishes to assure to religiously grounded conduct. RLPA defines a zone of private conduct and prohibits state laws from interfering in that zone. At the least, the analogy to the accepted practice of preemption is close enough that the Court would be ill-advised to extend the restrictions of Printz and New York to this legislation that simply displaces state law. It is possible that the Court would take its federalism agenda that far, but it would be a dramatic step beyond those two decisions.

    The Commerce Power does raise more questions of constitutional scope than the other aspects of RLPA. That is not a good reason to exclude it. I would emphasize again that broader coverage, based on several components, offers important benefits of fairness and neutrality, protecting as many religious practices as possible under the same standard.
 Page 74       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

D. ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE AND OTHER CONSTITUTIONAL ISSUES

    Some other constitutional issues merit shorter discussion. RLPA does not violate the Establishment Clause just because it protects religious exercise and not other kinds of conduct. In Corporation of Presiding Bishop v. Amos,(see footnote 53) the Court unanimously upheld the Title VII provision exempting religious organizations from Title VII's prohibition against religious discrimination in employment. The Court explicitly held that Congress may accommodate religious exercise even where the Free Exercise Clause does not compel it to do so.(see footnote 54) It also explicitly held that an accommodation of religious exercise need not ''come packaged with benefits to secular entities.''(see footnote 55) Numerous other decisions hold or state that legislatures may exempt religious practice from generally applicable laws.(see footnote 56)

    The fact that RLPA is a general accommodation, across a number of situations and laws rather than just one, has no effect on the Establishment Clause. The statute still does not establish religion just because it frees it from regulation; that interpretation would set the Establishment Clause at war with free exercise interests. Protection of religious conduct only constitutes an establishment if it shifts significant or disproprtionate costs from belief directly onto nonbelievers, or if the religious conduct so coincides with self-interest that offering the protection will induce others to practice (or claim to practice) religion. RLPA avoids those situations because it only prevents ''substantial'' burdens on religion and because disproportionate, direct costs will usually implicate a compelling governmental interest. Even assuming that a few of RLPA's applications would produce excessive favoritism for religion, they are not nearly enough to call the statute into question on its face.(see footnote 57) For these very reasons, the Eighth Circuit recently upheld RFRA itself, as applied to federal rather than state law, as against an Establishment Clause challenge.(see footnote 58)
 Page 75       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    It is worth noting that one other constitutional objection made against RFRA is simply inapplicable to RLPA. Some critics of RFRA claim that even its federal applications are unconstitutional because they do not rest on any single enumerated power and thus are merely an effort to reinterpret the Free Exercise Clause.(see footnote 59) That argument is mistaken as to RFRA. But it is manifestly inapplicable to RLPA, which rests on specific enumerated powers over spending, commerce, and Fourteenth Amendment violations, and which protects religious freedom in those classes of disputes alone.

E. EFFECT ON CIVIL RIGHTS LAWS

    Finally, I understand that concern has been raised about the effect that RLPA might have on the enforcement of civil rights laws prohibiting discrimination based on race, sex, or other characteristics. It is difficult to give such an opinion without the facts of a particular case, and moreover the supporters of RLPA have different views on how the statute would affect civil rights laws. But RLPA is presumably meant (like RFRA) to be mindful of the balancing analysis used in decisions before Employment Division v. Smith. That suggests at least a couple of points.

    First, in some cases the application of anti-discrimination laws to religious entities is quite likely to be found to rest on a compelling interest. For example, the Supreme Court held, before Smith, that there was a compelling interest in denying tax exemptions to schools that practiced racial discrimination on religious grounds.(see footnote 60) The interest was in denying any government support to racial discrimination in education, given the destructive history of such support in America.(see footnote 61) I have no doubt courts would reach the same result under RLPA.
 Page 76       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Second, however, the compelling interest test must also take account of all the factors in the particular case—not only the kind of discrimination, but the context in which it occurs and the nature of the government's restriction. Thus in Bob Jones the Court confined its decision to education, wisely leaving open questions such as whether a ''purely religious institution[ ],'' such as church, with sincere doctrinal beliefs could practice racial discrimination(see footnote 62)—for example, in its most fundamental religious operations such as the selection of clergy. Courts have properly barred government from intervening in the selection of clergy in all but exceptional cases. Some other civil rights laws serve less obviously compelling purposes than the prevention of racial discrimination. For example, it would be more difficult to show that the prevention of discrimination based on marital status is a compelling interest, since until few years ago cohabitation was the subject of widespread social and even legal condemnation. When religious landlords who refuse to rent to cohabiting couples have failed in their religious freedom claims, judges have sometimes said there was no ''substantial burden'' on the landlord's religious faith because her activity was purely commercial and profit-making.(see footnote 63) I disagree and would uphold the landlord's claim; but the lesson for present purposes is simply that RLPA claims, like those under RFRA, will have to be decided according to all of their circumstances.

    Mr. CANADY. Professor Eisgruber.

STATEMENT OF CHRISTOPHER L. EISGRUBER, PROFESSOR, NEW YORK UNIVERSITY SCHOOL OF LAW

 Page 77       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    Mr. EISGRUBER. Good morning. I would like to thank the committee for the opportunity to present my views this morning. I would also like to relay the thanks of my colleague and coauthor from the New York University School of Law, Professor Lawrence G. Sager. The testimony I present this morning is a result of a collaboration between the two of us, and he is fully in agreement with it.

    Professor Sager and I take an expansive view of congressional power. And more specifically, we believe that even under the doctrine of City of Boerne v. Flores, Congress retains substantial power to protect the interests and special needs of religious Americans, and that Congress can and should exercise that power. However, the central message of Boerne is this: that power must be exercised in a way that is done carefully and through tests that are appropriately drawn.

    It is our view that the Religious Liberty Protection Act that this committee is now considering repeats and exacerbates the mistakes that led eventually to the decision in Boerne that struck down RFRA. We don't believe that RLPA is a sensible measure for the protection of religious liberty, and we believe that it is virtually certain to be held unconstitutional if ever it reaches the Supreme Court.

    We have several objections to the statute. They are set out in detail in our written testimony and in greater detail in our academic work. I will, in my remarks this morning, confine myself to some of the objections that are related to the Federalism innovations made in the Religious Liberty Protection Act.

    The easiest way to understand the Federalism problems involved in the Religious Liberty Protection Act is to begin with the message of the Supreme Court in City of Boerne v. Flores. That message is substantially more generous to congressional power in this sphere than it is sometimes portrayed as being.
 Page 78       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    As I understand the Court's decision in City of Boerne v. Flores, the Court does not deny that Congress may reasonably concern itself with ferreting out conduct by State governments that is hostile to religious liberty, that is insensitive to the needs of religious Americans or that discriminates against religious Americans. The Supreme Court in City of Boerne struck down the Religious Freedom Restoration Act not because those goals were inappropriate goals for Federal legislation, but rather because, in the words of the Court, the test incorporated by the Religious Freedom Restoration Act, the compelling State interest test, was out of all proportion to the legitimate goals that Congress was pursuing. It was not congruent to those goals, the Court said.

    Congress might reasonably and effectively respond to the City of Boerne decision by enacting new legislation that uses a different test, one that is more nuanced to the goal of protecting religious interests against insensitivity, discrimination or hostility. Unfortunately, the Religious Liberty Protection Act this committee is now considering has not pursued that approach. RLPA does not abandon the compelling State interest test or modify it. Instead, RPLA simply moves it, looking for other portions of the constitutional test to which that particular test might be attached.

    I think the strategy is unwise. I think it is certain to be held unconstitutional should the issue ever reach the Supreme Court.

    This bill relies very heavily on both the spending power and the commerce power to justify the exercise of congressional power and the imposition of the compelling State interest test upon the States. If one takes the decision of the Court in the City of Boerne case seriously, I think it is exceedingly implausible that these strategies would survive judicial scrutiny. The committee's laudable concerns in enacting this legislation are concerns about religious liberty. They are concerns most appropriately articulated through the goals of the Fourteenth Amendment. They are not concerns about facilitating commerce or changing the nature of interstate commerce in any way. Nor are they goals that are in any easily understood fashion related to the extraordinary variety of spending programs that the Federal Government undertakes.
 Page 79       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    As we say in our testimony with respect to interstate commerce, religion is essentially a random vector. There is no reason to think that promoting religious conduct will increase, diminish, improve the quality of or affect in any other predictable way the interstate commerce of this country.

    In conclusion, Professor Sager and I both commend the goals of this committee and the goal of Congress more generally in legislating to protect the religious liberty of Americans. We believe, however, that the Religious Liberty Protection Act is an inappropriate vehicle for doing that, that it is unlikely to work well, and that it raises serious constitutional problems which, in our judgment, exacerbate those that the Religious Freedom Restoration Act possessed.

    Mr. CANADY. Thank you, Professor.

    [The prepared statement of Mr. Eisgruber follows:]

PREPARED STATEMENT OF CHRISTOPHER L. EISGRUBER, PROFESSOR, NEW YORK UNIVERSITY SCHOOL OF LAW

    We thank the Chair and the Committee for providing us with the opportunity to submit our views regarding the constitutionality of the ''Religious Liberty Protection Act'' (draft dated May 14, 1998) (hereafter, ''RLPA'').

    RLPA is a proposed effort to preserve what was valuable in the Religious Freedom Restoration Act (''RFRA''), which the Supreme Court held unconstitutional in City of Boerne v. Flores, 117 S.Ct. 2157 (1997).(see footnote 64) We believe that RLPA would perpetuate the constitutional mistakes of RFRA. Indeed, as presently drafted, RLPA has defects that would make it less rather than more constitutionally acceptable than was RFRA.
 Page 80       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

INTRODUCTION & BRIEF SUMMARY

    Religious liberty is a value of the highest order. In general, American public officials are sensitive to religious interests, and they often make commendable efforts to accommodate the needs of religious persons and practices. Nevertheless, there are undoubtedly times when officials—whether through prejudice, indifference, or misunderstanding—fail to show appropriate respect for the free exercise of religion. Congress has an important role to play in correcting these failures. If RLPA were a reasonable effort to discharge that responsibility, we would support it with enthusiasm.

    Unfortunately, RLPA does something entirely different. By generating an extreme form of the ''compelling state interest'' test, and imposing it over a more sweeping range of cases than has ever been contemplated by the Supreme Court or by Congress, RLPA would undermine the government's capacity to pursue perfectly legitimate, even-handed, democratically chosen goals. In effect, RLPA would two classes of citizens: those who have religious reasons for their actions and who would thereby be privileged to defy otherwise perfectly valid governmental regulations, and those whose reasons for acting—however laudable and heartfelt—are not religious. RLPA's compelling state interest test goes far beyond protecting religiously-motivated people from hostility or insensitivity. Taken seriously, it would make religiously-motivated persons sovereigns among us.

    Not surprisingly, Congress has no power to create the kind of special and arbitrary privileges that would result if RLPA were to become law. RLPA's peculiar statutory architecture amounts to a tacit admission of this problem: Even in an era when Congress retains broad license to act under its commerce clause and spending powers, RLPA stands out as depending upon a tenuous and improbable connection between those powers and the subject of religious liberty. Far from curing the constitutional vices of RFRA, RLPA's somewhat desperate hunt for constitutional authority proliferates such difficulties.
 Page 81       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Specifically, RLPA manifests five distinct constitutional vices. First, RLPA's sweeping application of the ''compelling state interest test'' unconstitutionally privileges religion. Because RLPA defines ''the exercise of religion'' in novel and unprecedented terms, it would likely violate the Establishment Clause even if its predecessor, RFRA, did not do so. Second, Section 2(a)(1) invokes Congress' spending power for purposes unrelated to the goals of any particular spending program. As a result, it exceeds the scope of Congress' enumerated powers. Third, Section 2(a)(2) likewise invokes Congress' commerce power for purposes unrelated to any goal related to interstate commerce. It, too, exceeds the scope of Congress' enumerated powers, and so would be held unconstitutional. Fourth, Section 3(b) limits the land use authority of state and local governments in a way that bears no relationship to any plausible claims that such governments are discriminating against religion. RLPA attempts to justify these limits by relying upon Congress' authority to enforce the Fourteenth Amendment. That effort is starkly inconsistent with the Supreme Court's decision in Flores. Fifth, Section 3(a) attempts to alter the judiciary's interpretation of the Free Exercise Clause. It thereby compromises the separation of powers and exceeds the authority of Congress under Section Five of the Fourteenth Amendment.

ANALYSIS

I. Establishment Clause Issues

    I.1. The Compelling State Interest Test. Like RFRA before it, RLPA incorporates the compelling state interest test. That test appears in Section 2(b) of RLPA, and it is the heart of the proposed legislation. We have criticized this test extensively. Christopher L. Eisgruber and Lawrence G. Sager, Why the Religious Freedom Restoration Act is Unconstitutional, 69 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 437 (1994); see also Christopher L. Eisgruber and Lawrence G. Sager, Congressional Power and Religious Liberty after City of Boerne v. Flores, 1997 S. Ct. Rev. 79 (1997). If honestly applied, the ''compelling state interest test'' is the most demanding standard known to constitutional law. Accordingly, the test is suitable only where it is appropriate to entertain a broad presumption of unconstitutionality—where, in other words, almost all of the cases that trigger the test will be abhorrent to the best standards of government behavior. Such a presumption rightly applies, for example, to laws intended to censor speech or to discriminate against racial or religious minorities. This presumption is badly suited to religious exemption cases, however. Many perfectly sound, even-handed laws will impose incidental burdens on some religious practices. The breadth and variety of religious belief make such collisions inevitable; but this does not offer a reason for depriving ourselves of the capacity to govern. Nor does the mere fact that a person's conduct is motivated by religious belief offer a good reason for permitting that person to defy reasonable, even-handed laws.
 Page 82       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    As applied in RFRA and RLPA, the ''compelling state interest test'' offers religiously motivated persons a sweeping privilege to disregard the laws that others are obliged to obey. It indefensibly favors religious commitments over the other deep concerns and interests of members of our society—concerns and interests like the welfare and integrity of one's family, deep moral and political commitments not recognizably grounded in religious beliefs, and professional, artistic and creative projects to which individuals may be passionately committed. Under RLPA or RFRA, for example, a church charity might ignore rules that a secular charity, devoted to identical causes, would have to respect. This sweeping preference for religiously motivated projects is a violation of the Establishment Clause of the First Amendment.

    The idea that some persons are entitled to ignore the laws that others are required obey, and that this privilege depends upon the actors' system of beliefs, is extraordinary and transparently inconsistent with our constitutional values. In the debate over RFRA, the degree to which this idea was alien to our constitutional tradition was obscured by a misreading of the Supreme Court's religious liberty jurisprudence in the three decades preceding the Court's decision in Department of Employment Services v. Smith, 474 U.S. 872 (1990). During that period, the Court gave lip-service to the proposition that government behavior that penalized persons for doing that which was essential to their religious commitments should be measured against the rigors of the compelling state interest test.

    Two crucially important facts went largely unobserved during the RFRA debate. First, while the Court spoke broadly, it acted extremely narrowly. Only one isolated group was ever permitted to defy a general legal rule on the basis of the compelling interest test. That was the Amish, who were permitted to direct the development of their teenage children outside the framework of what the State of Wisconsin recognized as a school. One other group prevailed in the Court's many pre-Smith exemptions cases. The Court protected people who were presumptively entitled to claim unemployment insurance benefits; who had deep religious reasons for refusing an available job; and who faced a serious danger that those reasons might be treated with hostility by state bureaucrats. Outside of these two small groups, every other attempt by any religious person or group to invoke the compelling state interest test failed. In every other branch of constitutional jurisprudence, the compelling state interest test was strict in theory, but fatal in fact; here it was strict in theory but notoriously feeble in fact. The Smith Court did not cause or even precipitate the test's demise. The Court merely announced what had long been true.
 Page 83       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    The second thing that went largely unobserved in the RFRA debate was the fact that RFRA—and now, even more, RLPA—proposed a much more sweeping form of the compelling state interest test than had ever been even the nominal rule in the Supreme Court. As the Court observed in Flores, RFRA imposed ''a least restrictive means requirement . . . that was not used in the pre-Smith jurisprudence RFRA purported to codify.'' 117 S. Ct. at 2171. Sections 2(b)(2) and 3(b)(1)(A) of RLPA repeat this innovation. As constitutional commentators widely recognize, the least restrictive means requirement is the element that gives the compelling state interest test its special rigor in other contexts. More significantly still, through its extraordinarily capacious definition of the exercise of religion RLPA extends the potential coverage of the compelling state interest test to a far wider range of cases than was ever contemplated by the Supreme Court's most sweeping statements. We explore the implications of this last observation in the section that follows.

    I.2. RLPA's Novel and Unprecedented Definition of the Exercise of Religion. RLPA exacerbates RFRA's Establishment Clause problems. Section 6(1) of RLPA defines ''religious exercise'' to mean ''an act or refusal to act that is substantially motivated by a religious belief, whether or not the religious exercise is compulsory or central to a larger system of religious belief.'' RLPA also amends RFRA to incorporate this new language. Section 7(a)(3). This definition is new. It appeared neither in RFRA nor in the Supreme Court's pre-Smith jurisprudence. Under RFRA, few courts had insisted that religious exercise be ''compulsory'' in order to trigger the statute's provisions, but most courts had held, in effect, that RFRA applied only to ''substantial burdens'' upon beliefs which were in some way and to some degree ''important'' to religious believers.(see footnote 65)
 Page 84       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    RLPA's definition of religious exercise threatens to increase the extent to which RFRA favored religion over non-religion. Under RFRA, it was possible to argue that a burden upon religious exercise was not ''substantial'' if it affected only optional practices for which adequate substitutes were available. For example, under RFRA, several churches running soup-kitchens in residential neighborhoods sought zoning exemptions which, they conceded, were unavailable to comparably situated secular charities. In these cases, it was possible to argue that no ''substantial burden'' upon religious practice existed: the churches were free to run soup-kitchens in other locations, and they were free to engage in other charitable practices which, as a matter of their own religious doctrine, were equally worthy. See, e.g., Daytona Rescue Mission, Inc. v. City of Daytona Beach, 885 F. Supp. 1554, 1560 (MD Fla. 1995). When successful, arguments of this kind mitigated the RFRA's favoritism for religion.

    It is not clear that these arguments would remain available under RLPA. To be sure, Sections 6(1) and 7(a)(3) define ''religious exercise,'' not ''substantial burden.'' Courts might find burdens upon religious exercise insubstantial if they affected only unimportant practices or if they left religious believers other, equally acceptable means by which to pursue their religious convictions. That construction of the ''substantial burden'' test, however, might render Section 7(a)(3) nugatory; if so, courts would be loathe to accept it. For that reason, RLPA exacerbates RFRA's already troubling disparity between the treatment of religious and non-religious interests. RLPA might fail to survive scrutiny under the Establishment Clause even if RFRA (without RLPA's amendments) could have done so.

II. Federalism Issues.

 Page 85       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    II.1. Spending Power Issues. Section 2(a)(1) of RLPA attempts to regulate the ability of state and local governments to ''substantially burden . . . religious exercise . . . in a program or activity . . . that receives federal financial assistance.'' That Section is an effort to draw upon Congress' spending power. The Supreme Court has held that Congress has broad discretion to impose conditions upon the use of federal money by state and local governments. The leading case is South Dakota v. Dole, 483 U.S. 203 (1987). In Dole, the Court upheld a statute which provided that states would lose federal highway funds if they did not raise the drinking age to 21. South Dakota objected to the statute on the ground that, under the Twenty-First Amendment, liquor laws were a matter of state rather than national control. The Supreme Court rejected this argument, reasoning that states could retain control over their drinking ages if they were willing to reject the offer of federal funds.

    The Court's construction of the spending power in Dole was generous, but it was not unlimited. The Court emphasized that ''our cases have suggested (without significant elaboration) that conditions on federal grants might be illegitimate if they are unrelated 'to the federal interest in particular national projects or programs.''' In Dole, the Court reasoned that ''the condition imposed by Congress is directly related to one of the main purposes for which highway funds are expended—safe interstate travel.'' By raising the drinking age, the Court suggested, states would further the purposes of federal transportation law. Yet, unless Dole's nexus requirement is entirely meaningless, RLPA cannot possibly satisfy it. RLPA applies to all religious conduct and it applies to all federal spending programs. It defies belief to think that accommodating religious conduct, regardless of its nature, supports the goals of every federal expenditure, regardless of its purpose. Indeed, RLPA's compelling state interest test is blatantly inconsistent with that idea: it would require states to accommodate religious conduct even at the expense of the core goals of any given program unless those goals rose to the level of a ''compelling state interest.''
 Page 86       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    In effect, RLPA assumes that once federal dollars touch some activity or program, the activity or program is federalized top-to-bottom: it then becomes fair game for congressional regulation regardless of whether the regulation has anything to do with the federal government's initial spending program. That is not what the Supreme Court said in Dole, and it is not a sensible reading of the Constitution.

    These considerations are sufficient to scuttle Section 2(a)(1) of RLPA, but it suffers from an additional constitutional defect. In Dole, states remained free to legislate whatever drinking age they preferred. If they departed from the federal standard, the penalty was forfeiture of federal funding. RLPA is not written that way. It does not provide that states will forfeit federal funds unless they enact state-law versions of RFRA or RLPA; instead, it subjects the states directly to private rights of action under federal law. This objection is somewhat technical in character, and there are ways around it. For example, the Court might construe RFRA as imposing conditions on every offer of funding which the national government makes to the states; on this theory, RLPA's regulation would effectively result from a ''contract'' between the states and the federal government, rather than from direct regulation by the federal government. It is not obvious, however, that this theory would or should succeed.(see footnote 66)

    II.2. Commerce Clause Issues. Section 2(a)(2) of RLPA attempts to regulate the ability of state and local governments to ''substantially burden religious exercise in or affecting commerce.'' That Section is an effort to draw upon Congress' commerce power. The Court has construed the commerce power generously including, of course, in connection with congressional efforts to prohibit discrimination. The case most often cited in this connection is Katzenbach v. McClung, 379 U.S. 294 (1964). In McClung, the Court upheld application of Title II of the Civil Rights Act of 1964 to Ollie's Barbecue, a restaurant in Birmingham, Alabama. The Court said Congress had power to prohibit race discrimination by Ollie's Barbecue on the following theory: by refusing to serve African-Americans, Ollie's Barbecue diminished the volume of business it did, and it thereby diminished demand for food products that moved in interstate commerce. The effect of one restaurant's actions might be small, but Congress was entitled to consider the aggregate effects of all restaurants similarly situated.
 Page 87       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    McClung grants Congress expansive authority, but that authority is not unlimited. Even in McClung, the Court insisted that Congress must identify some ''connection between discrimination and the movement of interstate commerce.'' The Court upheld Title II only because the legislative record included ''ample basis for the conclusion that . . . restaurants . . . sold less interstate goods because of . . . discrimination.'' It is impossible to imagine, much less substantiate, any such basis for RLPA. Religious conduct varies tremendously and unpredictably. From the standpoint of interstate commerce, religious activity is a random vector. There is no reason to believe that it promotes, diminishes, obstructs, or facilitates interstate commerce. Nor is there any reason to think that requiring government to accommodate religion would have any predictable effect whatsoever upon interstate commerce.

    The theory of Section 2(a)(2) of RLPA is largely parallel to the theory of Section 2(a)(1): it presupposes that once the congressional commerce power touches some activity or practice, that activity or practice becomes federalized top-to-bottom: it becomes fair game for congressional regulation regardless of whether the regulation has anything to do with promoting interstate commerce. That is not what the Supreme Court said in McClung. It is flatly inconsistent with the Supreme Court's recent decision in United States v. Lopez, 115 S.Ct. 1624 (1995), which held, inter alia, that Congress cannot regulate guns simply because they at one time entered the stream of interstate commerce.

    II.3. Issues Pertaining to Section Five of the Fourteenth Amendment. In Section 3(b), RLPA purports to limit the zoning authority of state and local governments. This Section of RLPA appears under the heading, ''Enforcement of the Free Exercise Clause.'' It is meant to apply to all land use cases, not just to those where the legislation's dubious invocations of the spending and commerce clause are apt. Apparently, this Section, like RFRA before it, depends for its validity on Congress' power to enforce the Fourteenth Amendment. That power was, of course, the focus of the Supreme Court's decision in Flores. There, the Court emphasized that Section Five does not permit Congress to displace the Court's judgments about the content of constitutional rights. Exercises of power under Section Five are valid only so long as they serve to put in place a scheme of remedies for rights which the Court itself is willing to recognize. Flores, 117 S. Ct. at 2163–64, 2171–72.
 Page 88       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    In Flores, the Court emphasized that ''Congress must have wide latitude in determining'' what measures are well-suited to remedy constitutional violations. Id., at 2164. Nevertheless, Section 3(b) of RLPA unquestionably repeats the vices that proved fatal to RFRA. Section 3(b) involves a sweeping and unwarranted federalization of local decision-making. It is no exaggeration to say that, under RLPA, any encounter between a religious organization and a local zoning authority would become a matter for federal adjudication. This remarkable preemption of local authority cannot be defended as a reasonable mechanism to remedy or prevent discrimination against religious interests. No doubt zoning administrators sometimes abuse their authority to harm unpopular churches. But that problem is not reasonably attacked by extending all churches—no matter how rich, how powerful, or how favored in law—a blanket writ to challenge the zoning ordinances which every other citizen and institution must respect. What the Court said about RFRA is equally true of Section 3(b) of RLPA: ''The stringent test [it] demands of state law reflects a lack of proportionality or congruence between the means adopted and the legitimate end to be achieved.'' 117 S. Ct. at 2171. Section 3(b) of RLPA is therefore starkly unconstitutional under Flores.

III. Separation of Powers Issues.

    Section 3(a) contains a remarkable assault on the judiciary's authority to make independent judgments about the meaning of the Constitution. It presumes, under the guise of enforcing the Fourteenth Amendment, to articulate ''presumptions'' which courts must respect when applying its First Amendment jurisprudence. In particular, the Section purports to increase the government's burden of persuasion in Free Exercise Clause cases. Because Section 3(a) attempts to deprive the courts of the authority to interpret the Constitution, it is patently unconstitutional. There are two doctrinal paths to that conclusion. The simplest runs through Flores. The Court said clearly in Flores that Congress may not use its Fourteenth Amendment powers to alter the substance of the Court's interpretations of the Fourteenth Amendment. Section 3(a) of RLPA offends this conclusion more blatantly than RFRA did, and the Court would undoubtedly find it unconstitutional.
 Page 89       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    There is, however, an even more fundamental doctrinal objection to Section 3(a). In United States v. Klein, 80 U.S. (3 Wall.) 128 (1871), the Supreme Court held that Congress may not specify a ''rule of decision'' for courts. Courts must be able to decide for themselves how to apply statutes or the Constitution. In the realm of statutory interpretation, Klein is difficult to apply: in some sense, of course, Congress specifies a ''rule of decision'' for courts every time it writes a statute. Christopher L. Eisgruber and Lawrence G. Sager, Why the Religious Freedom Restoration Act is Unconstitutional, 69 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 437, 470 (1994). RLPA, however, is a text-book violation of Klein. It attempts to compel judges to respect Congress' judgment, rather than their own, when interpreting the Constitution. And it forces judges to act as though they and adopted Congress' constitutional judgment as their own. Congress has the power and responsibility to arrive at its own view of constitutional substance, of course. But Congress is obliged to permit the Court this same independence of judgment.

CONCLUSION

    RLPA's constitutional defects are not technicalities. On the contrary, they all reflect strong claims on the policy judgment of the members of Congress who wish to act on behalf of religious liberty. Congress may well want to assure that religiously-motivated persons are treated fairly and that their interests are reasonably accommodated. But Congress surely does not want to sweepingly favor religiously-motivated persons over the vast majority of citizens conscientiously leading their lives, and to do so at the expense of the democratically-shaped rule of law. Likewise, Congress surely does not want to generate what Justice Kennedy in Flores correctly characterized as ''. . . a considerable intrusion into the States' traditional prerogatives and general authority to regulate for the health and welfare of their citizens.'' And finally, Congress should want to act as the Supreme Court's partner in the pursuit of political justice for American citizens, not as its adversary. That is the admirable tradition into which, for example, Title VII and the Voting Rights Act fall. RFRA was a false start, and Congress need not and should not perpetuate RFRA's mistakes.
 Page 90       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Of course, RFRA was motivated by a legitimate and important goal: the goal of assuring that religiously-motivated conduct is reasonably accommodated, that governmental actors are not insensitive or hostile to religious beliefs and commitments. Congress has an extremely important role to play in pursuing that goal. It can play that role in two different ways.

    First, Congress can continue to police state and federal conduct for egregious failures of the duty of reasonable accommodation and correct those failures. This is a role that Congress has traditionally played to the great benefit of constitutional justice in the United States. Thus, for example, Congress directed the armed forces to make reasonable accommodation for the wearing of religiously mandated apparel (see 10 U.S.C. 774); and thus, Congress withdrew funding for a Forest Service road that would have harmed a sacred Native American site (see House Committee on Appropriations, Dept. of the Interior and Related Agencies Appropriations Bill, 1989, H.R. Rep. No. 713, 100th Congress, 2d Sess. 72 (1988)); and thus, Congress has provided church employers with exemptions from certain tax obligations that are inconsistent with their religious beliefs (see 26 U.S.C. 3121(w)(1)); and thus, Congress acted to specifically assure members of the Native American Church the ability to use Peyote as part of their sacrament of worship (see 42 U.S.C. 1996). This effort requires ongoing vigilance and nuance of legislative response, but Congress' performance in this context has been superb.

    And second, Congress can enact more general legislation that offers broad protection to religiously-motivated persons against the possibility that their beliefs and commitments will be treated with insensitivity or hostility. This memorandum is not a good setting in which to explore the content of such legislation, but we would be glad to pursue the question with the Committee or any of its members.
 Page 91       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    What is critical to recognize for the moment is that RLPA is not such legislation. RLPA offers a distorted and untenable view of what religious liberty is, a view that Congress on reflection should not endorse; and RLPA streches notions of congressional authority to their breaking point, inviting the judicial articulation of constitutional limitations that Congress should not welcome. RLPA is unconstitutional, and if it were enacted, the Court would find it so to be. Congress has good reasons at the outset to choose a different vehicle to realize its altogether laudable concern for religious liberty.

Christopher L. Eisgruber
Professor of Law
New York University School of Law

Lawrence G. Sager
Robert B. McKay Professor of Law
New York University School of Law

    Mr. CANADY. Professor Hamilton.

STATEMENT OF MARCI HAMILTON, PROFESSOR, BENJAMIN N. CARDOZO SCHOOL OF LAW, YESHIVA UNIVERSITY

    Ms. HAMILTON. Good morning. And thank you to the committee, Mr. Chairman, and the members for inviting me to speak today.

 Page 92       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    I have spent the last 5 years thinking about religious liberty legislation, litigating it, and writing about it, and I am grateful for this opportunity to express my views.

    The U.S. Supreme Court, in Boerne v. Flores, said that Congress' declarations, its acts, only deserve deference when Congress takes responsibility to investigate independently the constitutionality of its actions. That, I think, is a very, very important message that the Court is sending Congress; that it must act with extreme care, and if it is going to act in the First Amendment arena, it must act with even more care than usual.

    H.R. 4019, the Religious Liberty Protection Act of 1998, is plainly unconstitutional. There is no question about it. It clearly violates the Separation of Powers. You need only read two cases to understand that. You need to read Boerne v. Flores and Marbury v. Madison. This is another attempt by Congress to rewrite the First Amendment. It is an attempt to amend the Constitution without Article V procedures. That cannot be done. It is not right, and it is not right for the people.

    Secondly, H.R. 4019 is a frontal assault on the States. Libertarians will tell you that the last bastion of liberty in the United States is local land use control. This bill will provide a blueprint for the Federal Government to regulate local government in every arena. There is no question that the decision by Congress to federalize local land use law would be a mistake from a constitutional perspective, but also a mistake from a policy perspective.

    Finally, the bill has no basis in any enumerated power. It cannot be enough for the Congress to say that religious liberty is important, and, therefore, all Federal financial assistance by the Federal Government has some nexus to a Federal interest.
 Page 93       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    I urge this body to get a comprehensive list from the GAO, the General Accounting Office, of every Federal dollar and where it lands, because if a government gets that dollar—because there is no dollar minimum in this bill—if it gets that dollar, it will then be regulated by this bill. This bill has enormous impact.

    I have asked my research assistants to start doing a list themselves of what will be the programs that will be affected by this bill. It is a huge project, and I urge you, Congress, to investigate it yourself as well.

    The Framers of the United States Constitution created this Congress to serve the Nation and the people. They made Members of Congress independent of the people. Members of Congress are not required to do what they are told; they have independent decision-making authority. It doesn't matter what faction or factions are in front of you; you are required by the Congress to act independently in the best interest of the Nation. James Madison, the leading structuralist framer, predicted that this experiment in democracy would not succeed if Members of Congress failed to act virtuously, and what he meant is if they failed to act for the greater good because they were captured by factions.

    In this area, more than any other, this area of religious liberty, it is absolutely essential that Congress investigate and acknowledge the source of this bill, and also its huge effect.

    In my written testimony, I provide a list of those groups in the society, those constituencies, that will be affected by this bill, perhaps unwittingly: Children, women in domestic violence situations, pediatricians who have labored hard for mandatory immunizations, the handicapped, women, minorities, homosexuals, departments of correction, artistic and historical preservation interests, neighborhoods, school boards, and State and local governments.
 Page 94       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    That is just the tip of the iceberg, and I urge you, this committee, to investigate the facts of the actual impact of this bill.

    Thank you very much.

    Mr. CANADY. Thank you, Professor Hamilton.

    [The prepared statement of Ms. Hamilton follows:]

PREPARED STATEMENT OF MARCI HAMILTON, PROFESSOR, BENJAMIN N. CARDOZO SCHOOL OF LAW, YESHIVA UNIVERSITY

    Thank you, Mr. Chairman, for inviting me to speak today on this important constitutional law topic. I am a Professor of Law at Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law, Yeshiva University, where I specialize in constitutional law. I was also the lead counsel for the City of Boerne, Texas in the case that ultimately invalidated the Religious Freedom Restoration Act (RFRA). See Boerne v. Flores, 117 S. Ct. 2157 (1997). I have devoted the last five years of my life to writing about, lecturing on, and litigating the Religious Freedom Restoration Act and similar religious liberty legislation in the states. For the record, I am a religious believer.

    As you know, the Boerne v. Flores decision unequivocally rejected RFRA. Not a single member of the Supreme Court defended the law in either the majority, the concurrences, or the dissents. The Court's decision was not a result of any hostility on the part of the Court toward this body. That is evident in its calm, evenhanded tone. Nor was it the result of mistaken understandings of its own precedents. The decision was inevitable. Contrary to Professor Laycock's and the Congressional Research Service's confident assurances in the RFRA legislative record, RFRA was plainly ultra vires.
 Page 95       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    I will not belabor RFRA's faults here, but rather refer you to the bibliography that follows this testimony. I also refer you to my letter of November 11, 1997 to Rep. Jerrold Nadler, which is attached, in which I explain the limited options open to Congress to aid religion.

    When I first read The Religious Liberty Protection Act of 1998, I thought someone was playing a prank on me. If I had been commissioned to write a law post-Boerne v. Flores that contains multiple constitutional violations, I could not have done a better job. There is no enumerated power that would support this bill. Moreover, it violates a score of structural constitutional principles.

    That this bill, which is a slap in the face of the Framers and the Constitution, is receiving a hearing indicates that what I say today may not make much difference. If Congress wants to be perceived as the savior of religious liberty and wants to defer to the most powerful coalition of religions in this country's history, there is absolutely nothing that I can do about it. Thus, I will not offer detailed critique of each of this bill's glaring constitutional errors. Instead, I will offer a summary of those errors.

    Then I will share with you the interests that will be hurt by granting religion this unprecedented quantum of power against the government.(see footnote 67) I represent none of these interests, but I have heard their stories in my travels around the country these five years.

RLPA'S MOST SEVERE CONSTITUTIONAL DEFECTS
 Page 96       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    RLPA Violates the Separation of Powers. Like RFRA, RLPA is an undisguised attempt to reverse the Supreme Court's interpretation of the Free Exercise Clause in Employment Division v. Smith, 494 U.S. 872 (1990), and to take over the Court's core function of interpreting the Constitution. See Secs. 2(a) and 3(a). For a clear discussion explaining why this is beyond Congress's power, see Boerne v. Flores, 117 S. Ct. at 2172.

    RLPA Violates the Constitution's Ratification Procedures. Like RFRA, RLPA attempts to amend the Constitution by a majority vote, bypassing Article V's required ratification procedures in direct violation of Marbury v. Madison, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137 (1803). For a plain discussion in which the Court reasserts its allegiance to Marbury, see Boerne v. Flores, 117 S. Ct. at 2168.

    RLPA Is an Assault on States' Rights. Despite its rote recitation of language from cases discussing federalism issues, see, e.g., Sec. 2(d) (''state policy not commandeered ''), this bill federalizes local land use law and (if good law) would eviscerate this final stronghold of local government. Local land control is one of the key elements of personal liberty. It violates the letter and the spirit of the modern Court's emerging structural constitutional jurisprudence. See Printz v. United States, 117 S. Ct. 2365 (1997); United States v. Lopez, 514 U.S. 549 (1995); New York v. U.S., 505 U.S. 144 (1992). If good law, RLPA's intervention in local land use law would set the pace for the most expansive invasion of state and local government authority in this nation's history.

 Page 97       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    If RLPA becomes law, it will haunt any representative who attempts to climb onto the limited federal government platform.

    RLPA Fails to Satisfy the Enumerated Power Requirement. RLPA is ultra vires. There is not a single statute that provides a model for RLPA's claim to be grounded in either the Spending Clause or the Commerce Clause. Congress has not identified any specific arena of spending or commerce. Rather, it has identified all religious conduct as its target and attempted to cover as much religious conduct as possible by casting a net over all federal spending and commerce. Like RFRA, its obvious purpose is to displace the Supreme Court's interpretation of the Free Exercise Clause in as many fora as possible. It is a transparent end-run around the Supreme Court's criticism of RFRA in Boerne v. Flores.

    RLPA Violates the Establishment Clause. RLPA privileges religion over all other interests in the society. While the Supreme Court indicated in Smith that tailored exemptions from certain laws for particular religious practices might pass muster, it has never given any indication that legislatures have the power to privilege religion across-the-board in this way.

    RFRA's and RLPA's defenders rely on Corporation of the Presiding Bishop v. Amos, 483 U.S. 327 (1987), for the proposition that government may enact exemptions en masse. This is a careless reading of the case, which stands for the proposition that religion may be exempted from a particular law (affecting employment) if such an exemption is necessary to avoid excessive entanglement between church and state. RLPA, like RFRA, creates, rather than solves, entanglement problems. RLPA, which was drafted by religion for the purpose of benefitting religion and has the effect of privileging religion in a vast number of scenarios, violates the Establishment Clause. For the Court's most recent explanation of the Establishment Clause, see Agostini v. Felton, 117 S. Ct. 1997 (1997).
 Page 98       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    The following is a list of interests that will be affected adversely if RLPA is adopted, because it elevates religion above all other societal interests. As Oregon recently discovered when a prosecutor attempted to prosecute a religious community for the death of three children, particular exemptions from general laws can have real consequences. Before blindly passing this law with its mandate to exempt religion from general laws in an infinite number of scenarios, Congress should know that it risks responsibility for harming the following constituencies:

 Children in religions that advocate and practice abuse

 Women in religions that advocate male domination

 Children in religions that refuse medical treatment, including immunizations

 Pediatricians, who have lobbied vigorously for mandatory immunizations

 The handicapped, women, minorities, and homosexuals, whose interests are currently protected by antidiscrimination laws and may well be trumped by religions exercising the compelling interest/least restrictive means test

 Departments of correction and prison officials attempting to ensure order in prisons populated by increasingly violent criminals

 Artistic and historical preservation interests, including whole communities that depend on historical districts for revenue and jobs
 Page 99       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

 Neighborhoods attempting to enforce neutral rules regulating congestion, building size, lot size, and on- and off-street parking

 School boards desperately attempting to ensure order and safety in the public schools

 State, local, and municipal officials who will be forced to bear the cost of accommodating every religious request (whether from a mainstream religion or a cult) or bear the cost of litigating refusals to do so

 Last, but not least, citizens who will bear the extreme increase in litigation costs created by these new rights coupled to an attorney's fees provision (a virtual invitation to sue)

    In sum, RLPA is no better than RFRA. In fact, it is worse. Congress has a duty to investigate its wide-ranging effects with care before taking this plainly unconstitutional path.

    For those who take comfort from the fact that RLPA is supported by a wide cross-section of religions, I leave you with the words of Framer Rufus King, one of the youngest members of the Constitutional Convention but a Harvard graduate who was highly respected on structural issues: ''[I]f the clergy combine, they will have their influence on government.''

    Bibliography of works by Marci A. Hamilton addressing the Religious Freedom Restoration Act and Boerne v. Flores:
 Page 100       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

The Religious Freedom Restoration Act Is Unconstitutional, Period, 1 U. PENN. J. CONSTL. L. 1 (1998).

Boerne v. Flores: A Landmark for Structural Analysis, 39 WM. &699 (1998).

Religion's Reach,
CHRISTIAN CENTURY 644 (July 16–23, 1997).

The Constitution's Pragmatic Balance of Power Between Church and State, 2 NEXUS, A JOURNAL OF OPINION 33 (1997).

The Religious Freedom Restoration Act: Letting the Fox into the Henhouse Under Cover of Section Five of the Fourteenth Amendment, 16 CARDOZO L. REV. 357 (1994).

The Constitutional Rhetoric of Religion,—U. ARK. AT LITTLE ROCK L. REV.—(forthcoming 1998).


Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law,
Yeshiva University,
New York, NY, November 11, 1997.
Hon. JERROLD NADLER,
Committee on the Judiciary,
House of Representatives, Washington, DC.

 Page 101       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    DEAR REPRESENTATIVE NADLER: Thank you for asking me to comment on the measures that Congress could take to ensure religious liberty. I am a legal scholar who teaches and specializes in constitutional law and First Amendment issues at Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law, Yeshiva University. Over the last several years, I have spent the vast majority of my time studying, writing, and speaking about the Religious Freedom Restoration Act. As lead counsel for the City of Boerne, Texas before the United States Supreme Court, I was instrumental in the invalidation of the Religious Freedom Restoration Act. See Boerne v. Flores, 117 S. Ct. 2365 (1997).

    I understand that various members of Congress are now interested in providing some protection for religious liberty in ways that accord with the Constitution. I am happy to provide my insights into this difficult project.

    I have divided my remarks into three sections. First, I will address the question whether current Supreme Court doctrine leaves religion unprotected and therefore justifies congressional action at this time. My answer is ''no.'' Second, I will provide some background guidance on the structure of the Constitution and its implications for congressional regulation of religious liberty. Finally, I will turn to potential means by which Congress could effect religious liberty and explain why various proposals will face difficult constitutional challenges.

I. THE STATE OF RELIGIOUS LIBERTY UNDER EMPLOYMENT DIV. V. SMITH

    The impetus for the Religious Freedom Restoration Act (''RFRA'') was the outcry against the United States Supreme Court's decision in Employment Div. v. Smith, 494 U.S. 872 (1990). The decision was met with loud complaints from religions, civil liberties groups, and some legal scholars, who claimed (erroneously, in my view) that free exercise claims were treated demonstrably better under the law preceding Smith.
 Page 102       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    In fact, the Smith standard is not as bad and the pre-Smith case law is not as good for religion as they have been depicted.

    Before Smith, the Supreme Court applied a context-dependent balancing approach in free exercise cases. That is, it applied a range of standards of review, depending on the context. Different standards were applied in the military, prison, government services, government lands, and unemployment compensation cases. At no time did the Court require the compelling interest test in every free exercise case. Moreover, the Court has never applied the ''least restrictive means'' test in its free exercise cases. The Court says as much in the Boerne decision. 117 S. Ct. at 2171.

    The legislative history of RFRA makes it abundantly clear that Congress understood that it was enacting a law that protected religion significantly more than the Supreme Court's pre-Smith case law. At one point, Representative Henry Hyde proposed an amendment to RFRA for the purpose of transforming RFRA into an actual ''restoration'' statute. That amendment was defeated and Congress was on plain notice that it was not simply adopting the Court's pre-Smith case law. Rather, it was giving more to religion than it had ever received under the Court's free exercise doctrine. In addition, the Congressional Research Service's Reports made it clear that RFRA would exceed the Court's pre-Smith case law.

    Thus, the claim that legislative action is needed to ''restore'' previous federal law is a red herring. The outcry against the Smith decision was based on false presuppositions about the Court's free exercise jurisprudence. While protecting religious belief absolutely, the Court traditionally has disfavored free exercise claims impinging on religious conduct. See Marci A. Hamilton, The Belief/Conduct Paradigm in the Supreme Court's Free Exercise Jurisprudence: A Theological Account of the Failure to Protect Religious Conduct, 54 Ohio St. L.J. 713, 746–49 (1993). Indeed, the Smith decision is not demonstrably worse for religion than the preceding case law, and it certainly does not signal the end of religious liberty.
 Page 103       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    The Smith decision does not leave religion in as unprotected a position as those advocating federal regulation insist. The Court holds that the Constitution does not require exemptions for religious conduct burdened by neutral, generally applicable law, which is a fair summary of its preceding case law. The decision also provides a variety of additional theories on which one could peg a religious liberty claim.

    The following are the means by which current Supreme Court precedent protects religious liberty:

  1. As the Supreme Court stated in its first free exercise decision, Reynolds v. United States, 98 U.S. 145 (1879), religious belief is absolutely and categorically protected. This is a principle that was reaffirmed in Smith and has never been questioned in any Supreme Court decision.

  2. Discrimination against and persecution of religion is forbidden. Any law that is not neutral and generally applicable receives the strictest scrutiny under the Court's decision in Church of the Lukumi Babalu Ave, Inc. v. City of Hialeah, 508 U.S. 520 (1993). As I read that case, strict scrutiny in this context is strict in theory and fatal in fact. Moreover, even when a law looks neutral, the Court will inquire into whether it is in fact neutral and generally applicable. The targeting of a religion or religion in general for deleterious treatment violates the Free Exercise Clause, period.(see footnote 68)

  3. Strict scrutiny may be appropriate in instances where there is ''individualized governmental assessment.'' Smith, 494 U.S. at 884. This notion echoes various First Amendment cases involving the freedom of speech and officials with unfettered discretion and has yet to be developed in the courts.
 Page 104       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

  4. Combined, or ''hybrid,'' constitutional claims are subject to strict scrutiny. Smith, 494 U.S. at 881–82.

  5. Lawmakers are encouraged to provide exemptions for religious conduct burdened by generally applicable laws. Smith, 494 U.S. at 890.

    In sum, the Court's decision in Smith is more complicated and more favorable to religious liberty than its opponents have acknowledged. Moreover, we simply do not know how the Smith rules are likely to play out in the courts. The Religious Freedom Restoration Act was passed only three years after Smith was decided, which was insufficient time for any significant number of cases to make their way through the trial and appellate courts. Under the current state of federal law, a wait-and-see attitude is the wisest course for Congress. The situation is not as dire as the legislatures are being told.

II. THE STRUCTURE OF THE CONSTITUTION AND CONGRESSIONAL POWER TO REGULATE RELIGIOUS LIBERTY

    Congress has authority to pursue national interests through a discrete set of enumerated powers found in Article I. It has also the authority to enforce constitutional rights that are violated or very likely to be violated by the states under Section 5 of the Fourteenth Amendment. The Religious Freedom Restoration Act was invalidated on separation of powers, Article V, and federalism grounds because it did not enforce constitutional guarantees but rather attempted to redefine them.

    There is no constitutional provision like Section 5 of the Fourteenth Amendment that permits Congress to enforce liberty guarantees against itself. A particular federal law might have the effect of easing a burden on religious conduct, but that law will stand or fall depending on whether it is a valid exercise of an enumerated power. See, e.g., Heart of Atlanta Motel, lnc. v. United States, 379 U.S. 241 (1964).
 Page 105       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    The Congress is limited to acting under a substantive, enumerated power. It is not enough for Congress to invoke the Necessary and Proper Clause, which was characterized by the Court last Term as the ''last, best hope of those who defend ultra vires congressional action.'' Printz v. United States, 117 S. Ct. 2365, 2378 (1997). If the constitutional base of its action is not ''visible to the naked eye,'' Congress is obligated to demonstrate through findings or by explanation the constitutional source of its action. United States v. Lopez, 514 U.S. 549, 563 (1995).

    Thus, if Congress is inclined to protect religious liberty, it has one of two options: it can identify violations of the guarantees of the Free Exercise Clause by the states and enact a law aimed at enforcing those guarantees under Section 5 of the Fourteenth Amendment or it can act pursuant to an enumerated power.

    Even if Congress acts upon a constitutional base, e.g., under an enumerated power or Section 5, its enactment will still face serious constitutional challenge under the Establishment Clause of the First Amendment. Congress may not act for the purpose of benefitting (or inhibiting) religion and its actions must not have the effect of benefitting (or inhibiting) religion. See Agostini v. Felton, 117 S. Ct. 1997 (1997).

    The principle that Congress must act very carefully when it is urged to act pursuant to requests from religion is evident in the story of RFRA's enactment and invalidation. RFRA bad both the purpose and the effect of benefitting religion. As Justice Stevens stated in Boerne regarding RFRA, ''[t]his governmental preference for religion, as opposed to irreligion, is forbidden by the First Amendment.'' 117 S. Ct. at 2172 (Stevens, J., concurring).
 Page 106       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Congress should take little comfort from the fact that other Justices did not join Justice Stevens' concurrence in Boerne. The concurrence was unnecessary to reach a decision in the case; there were six votes in the majority to invalidate RFRA on separation of powers and federalism grounds and an additional seventh vote (Justice O'Connor) for the reasoning of the majority on those issues. Indeed, no member of the Court criticized or even referred to Justice Stevens' concurrence, and several members of the Court at oral argument were plainly concerned that RFRA violates the rule against benefitting religion over irreligion.

III. THE POSSIBLE MEANS BY WHICH CONGRESS MIGHT REGULATE RELIGIOUS LIBERTY AND THEIR CONSTITUTIONAL VIRTUES AND DEFECTS

    The following suggests options for congressional action regarding religious liberty and their likely constitutional problems and virtues:

  1. Section 5 of the Fourteenth Amendment. If, after due consideration, Congress were able to identify an arena in which religious conduct is subject to (or is highly likely to be subject to) unconstitutional burdens, Congress would have the power to enact laws for the purpose of enforcing the Fourteenth Amendment's due process clause. Congress may not go forward, however, unless there is evidence that the states have engaged in or are likely to engage in behavior that unconstitutionally burdens religious conduct. See Boerne, 117 S. Ct. at 2166 (citing the Civil Rights Cases, 109 U.S. 3 (1883)). If an actual or imminent violation of the Constitution is evident on its face, the Court can take judicial notice of it, but the restraints of federalism forbid the validation of legislative action against the states unless the claims to constitutional violations are self-evident or documented. RFRA was built on the weakest of foundations under these requirements, because no imminent constitutional violations were self-evident and none (at least within the last 40 years) were documented. The legislative record for RFRA fell far short of what would be needed to support Section 5 legislation regarding religious liberty at this time in our nation's history. Id. at 2169.
 Page 107       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

  2. Commerce Clause. The Commerce Clause has become one of the most elastic of Congress's powers, though the Court has begun to articulate some meaningful boundaries to the power. Under United States v. Lopez, 514 U.S. 549 (1995), the Congress may regulate activity only if the activity has a ''substantial relation to interstate commerce.'' 514 U.S. at 559. ''Where economic activity substantially affects interstate commerce, legislation regulating that activity will be sustained.'' 514 U.S. at 560. The Court was unwilling to uphold the Gun-Free School Zones Act of 1990 because the Court ''would have been required to pile inference upon inference in a manner that would bid fair to convert congressional authority under the Commerce Clause to a general police power of the sort retained by the States.'' 514 U.S. at 567.

  In addition, there are federalism limits on the exercise of the Commerce Clause. Congress may not regulate in areas that traditionally have been left to local control. 514 U.S. at 567–68 (emphasizing importance of ''distinction between what is truly national and what is truly local'').

  I understand that it has been proposed that Congress might regulate local zoning laws for the benefit of religion pursuant to the Commerce Clause. Any attempt to federalize local land use law is likely to be greeted with a chilly reception in the courts, especially the Supreme Court. The only arena that has been left almost exclusively to local control is land use. If there is a Commerce Clause power to regulate religion, I strongly doubt that it lies in land use regulation.

  3. Spending Clause. Some have proposed that Congress might enact spending legislation in which Congress conditions federal receipt of funds, for example, highway funds, on the adoption of the RFRA standard in the courts of that state. Not to state the matter too bluntly, but it is my firm conviction that this is tantamount to waving a red flag to a bull.
 Page 108       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

  In South Dakota v. Dole, 483 U.S. 203 (1987), the Court upheld a law that permitted the Secretary of Transportation to withhold highway funds from states in which minors under 21 could purchase alcohol. Per Chief Justice Rehnquist, the Court upheld the law as an appropriate exercise of Congress's power under the Spending Clause because there was a reasonable connection between driving, drinking, and the legitimate national goal of highway safety. Justice O'Connor dissented on the ground that the nexus between highway funds and underage drinking laws was too attenuated to pass constitutional muster under the Spending Clause.

  Because the relationship is so obviously distant, any attempt to condition highway spending on issues involving religious liberty are likely to invite the Court to revisit its pronouncements in South Dakota v. Dole and to move closer to Justice O'Connor's position.

  4. Exemptions. Congress might consider whether national exemptions are appropriate with respect to particular burdens on religious conduct imposed by federal law. The history of Goldman v. Weinberger, 475 U.S. 503 (1986), provides helpful guidance. In that case, the Court held that the military was not constitutionally required to permit the wearing of yarmulkes in violation of a generally applicable rule governing military uniforms. Congress followed the decision with a targeted exemption for headgear for religious purposes. That exemption was the sort of exemption envisioned by the Court in Smith.

  Congressional exemptions are only constitutional to the extent that the exemption is crafted through the appropriate exercise of one of Congress's enumerated powers and only if the exemption is in the national interest intended to be served by that particular enumerated power. Congress does not have general, plenary authority to aid religion through exemptions. Such an approach would violate the enumerated powers requirement and, most likely, the Establishment Clause.
 Page 109       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

  I would not urge Congress to consider exemptions that would apply to state law, because such exemptions may well violate the inherent principles of federalism at the core of the Constitution. In contrast, state and local governments have a freer hand to provide exemptions because they hold the very sort of generalized lawmaking authority not permitted Congress. It should be noted, though, that state and local government exemptions will likely face Establishment Clause challenges.

    As the foregoing indicates, the Framers crafted a constitutional scheme that makes it difficult for the federal government to act in a way that benefits religion. Whatever law is considered is due the most careful scrutiny as Congress navigates these appropriately difficult waters between Scylla and Charybdis.

CONCLUSION

    At this stage in the history of religious liberty in the United States, I strongly urge Congress to stop, look, and listen. It makes sense to take a breather from legislative action regarding religion for a reasonable period of time so that the courts can work out the meaning of the various aspects of the decision in Employment Div. v. Smith and so that a more detailed record of the need for such legislative action can be built. The case for legislative action may be weakened considerably as the doctrine is developed.

    Hasty action, taken at the behest of organized religion, is likely to lead to invalidation on either an enumerated powers or an Establishment Clause theory. Congress should act in this terribly sensitive area only if it has sound knowledge and understanding of the state of religious liberty and the members are firmly persuaded that a real problem exists. No matter what tack Congress takes in the area, it would be prudent to build a persuasive legislative record.
 Page 110       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Finally, if Congress were to decide to bide its time, it may take some comfort in the Framers' views of religious liberty. The Framers did not believe that religion is always an unalloyed good for society or that the state is always in error when it burdens religious conduct. To the contrary, the Framers intended to achieve a pragmatic balance of power between church and state. At the Constitutional Convention, James Madison considered religious sects as factions that have the capacity to do good and the capacity to exceed their appropriate boundaries. Society will be best served if Congress listens to the concerns of religious interests with care but only if the legislature engages its independent judgment in evaluating those concerns.

    Thank you for this opportunity to share my views with you. I would be happy to discuss these general issues or any particular proposal with you at your convenience.

Sincerely,
Marci A. Hamilton, Professor of Law.


    Mr. CANADY. Mr. Schaerr.

STATEMENT OF GENE SCHAERR, ATTORNEY, SIDLEY & AUSTIN, WASHINGTON, DC

    Mr. SCHAERR. Thank you. Good morning, Mr. Chairman and members of the committee. Today I would like to explain why I believe the constitutional objections that have been raised to this proposed legislation are, in my view, clearly misguided and why the act is very likely to be upheld if it is challenged, once it is enacted.
 Page 111       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    If time permits, I would also be happy to explain why, as a conservative Republican concerned about issues of Federalism, I believe the act is an appropriate use of Federal power and why I believe it will provide significant protections for religious freedom.

    One key reason why the key provisions of the act are likely to be upheld is that unlike RFRA, this legislation's key provisions are tied to the Supreme Court's own interpretation of the Constitution. For example, the reach of Section 2(a)(1), which imposes a compelling interest test on government decisions in or affecting interstate or foreign commerce, that provision necessarily depends on the Supreme Court's view of the extent of Congress' power to regulate such commerce.

    It is like a statutory accordion. It can bring within its sweep more or fewer government decisions, as the Supreme Court's interpretation of the commerce power expands or contracts. And in part, for that reason, I think it is most unlikely that that provision could ever be invalidated as exceeding Congress' commerce power. Something that is beyond Congress' commerce power simply won't be included in the statute at all.

    And contrary to Professor Eisgruber's suggestion, the Lopez decision does not require that legislation promote or regulate commerce per se in order to fall within Congress' power. All it requires is that the subject matter of the legislation have some substantial effect on interstate commerce.

    Now, the same is true of Section 3(a), which in some ways could be the most important provision of this legislation. That provision takes the Supreme Court's view about the scope of the Free Exercise Clause as a given, and then it simply makes it easier to enforce whatever free exercise rights the Supreme Court is willing to recognize. And it does that, for example, by specifying that the government has the burden of proof on certain issues in litigation.
 Page 112       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Now, again, like an accordion, this provision would also expand or contract if the Supreme Court's interpretation of the Free Exercise Clause expands or contracts in the future, but it is certainly not unconstitutional. And this is just the kind of thing that the Flores decision said that Congress clearly can do under section 5 and the kind of thing Congress has always done in the area of civil rights. It is clearly proportionate, to use the words of the Flores decision, to the legitimate goal of enforcing the Free Exercise Clause.

    And with all respect to Professor Eisgruber, again his argument that section 3(a) violates the Separation of Powers by allocating the burden of proof to the government defendants on most issues, that argument in my view is frivolous. There is no case law support for it, and it is refuted by Supreme Court decisions upholding Congress' power to do just that in constitutional civil rights cases. If the Court were to adopt his argument, a whole wide swath of the civil rights laws would fall.

    Now, to the extent that the act relies upon section 5 to reach beyond what the Supreme Court recognizes as a constitutional violation, the legislation also does that in a way that the Flores decision said was appropriate. Flores said that Congress has the power under section 5 to enforce the Free Exercise Clause through substantive legislation on two conditions: First of all, that there is reason to believe that many of the laws affected by the new law have a significant likelihood of being unconstitutional; and, second, there has to be a congruence or a proportionality between the injury to be prevented and the means adopted to that end.

 Page 113       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    Now, the land use restrictions in section 3(b) simply follow that road map that the Supreme Court gave us in Flores. There is in the record strong evidence that land use decisions are being used to discriminate against religious minorities, and we will hear more testimony about that later today. And this type of discrimination is clearly unconstitutional, and yet it is very difficult to detect and prevent.

    And so the act's remedy, which requires that land use regulations satisfy a kind of compelling interest test, is certainly proportion—excuse me, proportional to and congruent with the injury that has been documented in this record of this legislation and will be further documented today.

    And unlike RFRA, the remedy under section 3(b) is limited to a very defined class of particularly problematic government decisions.

    Now, to the extent that the act relies upon Congress' Spending Power, it also does that in a way that is uncontroversial. For example, under Title VI of the Civil Rights Act, Congress has long required that State participants in Federal programs not engage in racial discrimination. No one could seriously question the validity of that condition under the Spending Clause. So, too, here. Section 2(a)(2), which is the Spending Clause provision, simply requires that all those, State and private entities, all those who operate federally-funded programs respect religious freedom in the administration of those programs, and that is no different in principle from Title VI.

    It is also, in my view, even easier to defend than the law that was upheld in South Dakota v. Dole. As you will recall, that law permitted the Secretary of Transportation to withhold all highway funds from a State if it did not have a law on its books that prohibited minors from purchasing alcohol. So in that case, the Federal Government was essentially forcing the States to take action that was separate from their operation of a federally-funded program, and the Federal Government required that as a condition of their being able to operate those programs. It would be kind of like if Congress directed the States to enact their own miniature RFRA as a condition of participating in the Medicaid program.
 Page 114       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    But that is obviously not what this provision in this legislation does. In this legislation, the spending condition, namely respecting religious freedom, applies only on a program-by-program basis and does not require the State to take any external action at all.

    I think the Establishment Clause issue has been adequately addressed.

    Finally, on the issue of Separation of Powers, I also believe that argument is weaker here than a similar argument that Ms. Hamilton made in the Flores case, and which got no votes in the United States Supreme Court, and was, in fact, recently rejected by the Eighth Circuit Court of Appeals in the case of Christians v. Crystal Evangelical Free Church. Now, yes, there is no question that Justice Kennedy's majority opinion in Flores discussed Separation of Powers principles, but it did so only in the context of justifying the Court's interpretation of section 5. The Court did not suggest or certainly hold that RFRA violated separation of powers principles in addition to being beyond Congress' authority under section 5.

    One other point about this legislation. Unlike RFRA, this act does not purport to be a full-blown restoration by Congress of the rules that were applicable to free exercise claims prior to the Smith decision. So no one can plausibly claim, in my view, that Congress, in this legislation, would somehow be trying to second-guess or overrule the Supreme Court on the proper interpretation of the Constitution; and, therefore, in my view, there is no plausible argument that this is in effect an amendment of the Constitution that requires ratification.

 Page 115       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    Thank you.

    Mr. CANADY. Thank you, Mr. Schaerr.

    [The prepared statement of Mr. Schaerr follows:]

PREPARED STATEMENT OF GENE SCHAERR, ATTORNEY, SIDLEY & AUSTIN, WASHINGTON, DC

    Good morning Mr. Chairman and members of the Committee. I am honored to appear before this Committee in the company of such distinguished legal scholars and to discuss the proposed Religious Liberty Protection Act (''the Act'').

    During the past five years, I have had the privilege of representing a number of Senators and Congressmen in their efforts to defend the Religious Freedom Restoration Act (or ''RFRA'') in court, including the Supreme Court in the Flores case. I can report that we have done quite well so far in defending RFRA as it applies to the federal government—but, as you know, not quite so well in defending it as applied to state and local governments. And that is why the Religious Liberty Protection Act is needed.

    Today I would like to respond to one major concern that has been expressed in some circles: that passage of the Act will be futile because the Supreme Court is likely to strike it down on federalism-related grounds, just as the Court invalidated the state portion of RFRA. As I will explain in a moment, I believe that concern is misguided. And, as a conservative Republican—and one who served in the White House during the last Republication Administration—I will also briefly explain why I believe the Act is an appropriate use of federal regulatory power, and why I believe it will provide significant protection for religious freedom.
 Page 116       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

WILL THE ACT BE UPHELD?

    The principal constitutional arguments against RLPA have been ably refuted by Professor Laycock and others, so I will not repeat the analysis in detail. But let me emphasize a few of the key reasons why I believe those arguments will not be adopted by the Supreme Court.

    First, unlike RFRA, many of the Act's central provisions are tied to the Supreme Court's own interpretation of the Constitution. For example, the reach of Section 2(a)(1)—which imposes the compelling interest test on government decisions ''in or affecting'' interstate or foreign commerce—necessarily depends on the Supreme Court's view of the extent of Congress's power to regulate such commerce. Like an accordion, that provision could bring within its sweep more or fewer government decisions as the Supreme Court's interpretation of the commerce power expands or contracts. But I think it most unlikely that the provision itself could be invalidated as exceeding Congress's commerce power.

    The same is true of Section 3(a). That provision takes the Supreme Court's views on the scope of the Free Exercise Clause as a given, and then simply makes it easier to enforce whatever free exercise rights the Court is willing to recognize. Thus, like Section 2(a)(1), this section could also expand or contract if the Supreme Court's interpretation of the Free Exercise Clause expands or contracts in the future. And for that reason, I don't think anyone could plausibly argue that this provision exceeds Congress's authority under Section 5 of the Fourteenth Amendment. To the contrary, this is just the kind of thing the Flores decision said Congress can always do under Section 5.(see footnote 69)
 Page 117       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Second, to the extent the Act relies upon Section 5 to reach beyond what the Supreme Court recognizes as violations of the Free Exercise Clause, it does so in precisely the way Flores said was appropriate. In Flores, the Court explicitly recognized that Congress has the power under Section 5 to enforce the protections of the Fourteenth Amendment through substantive or even ''preventive'' legislation where two conditions are satisfied: (1) ''there is reason to believe that many of the laws affected by the congressional enactment have a significant likelihood of being unconstitutional''; and (2) there is ''a congruence and proportionality between the injury to be prevented or remedied and the means adopted to that end.''(see footnote 70)

    The land-use restrictions contained in the Act are a prime example of legislation that is constitutional under this formula. Land-use regulation is usually administered through highly individualized processes, often without regard to generally applicable rules. As the legislative record shows, there is strong evidence that these processes have been and are repeatedly being used throughout the United States to discriminate against religious minorities, denying them houses of worship in communities where they—and perhaps religion in general—are unpopular. This type of discrimination is clearly unconstitutional, but is often extremely difficult to detect and prevent.

    For this reason, it is entirely appropriate for Congress to adopt the kind of remedy embodied in Section 3(a). That remedy—requiring that the regulation be the least restrictive means to prevent substantial and tangible harm to the government's compelling interest—is certainly ''proportional'' to and congruent with the constitutional injury documented in the record. Unlike RFRA, the remedy is limited to a defined class of particularly problematic government decisions, and does not apply more broadly. Thus, the land-use provisions of the Act simply follow the road map laid down in Flores, and I think the Supreme Court will recognize that if anyone challenges them.
 Page 118       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Third, the Act's limited abrogation of sovereign immunity for violations of the Free Exercise Clause is constitutionally uncontroversial even under recent Supreme Court precedent. That is because this aspect of the Act is based on the Fourteenth Amendment rather than a constitutional provision pre-dating the Eleventh Amendment.(see footnote 71) And the abrogation of sovereign immunity here is similar to those contained in the civil rights laws.(see footnote 72) Moreover, in this regard the Act simply treats state governments the same as the federal government, which is also deprived of its sovereign immunity as to free exercise claims.

    Fourth, to the extent the Act relies upon Congress's spending power, it does so in a way that is similarly uncontroversial. Congress has frequently attached conditions to the use of federal funds to ensure that such funds are not used in a manner that undermines the interests of the United States or the rights of its citizens. For example, under Title VI of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, Congress has long required that state participants in federal programs not engage in racial discrimination,(see footnote 73) and no one could seriously question the validity of that requirement under the Spending Clause.

    So too here: Section 2(a)(2) simply requires that all those who operate federally funded programs respect religious freedom in the administration of those programs. That is no different in principle from Title VI.

    It is also far easier to defend than the law that was upheld in South Dakota v. Dole,(see footnote 74) and which permitted the Secretary of Transportation to withhold all highway funds from states in which minors could purchase alcohol. There, the federal government essentially forced the states to take action that was entirely separate from operating federally funded programs as a condition of participating in those programs—kind of like forcing the states to enact religious-freedom legislation as a condition of participating in Medicaid. Here, by contrast, the spending condition—respecting religious freedom—applies only on a program-by-program basis, and does not require the state to take any external action.(see footnote 75)
 Page 119       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Fifth, because RLPA is narrower than RFRA, the Establishment Clause argument against the Act is even weaker than the Establishment Clause argument that garnered only one vote in Flores. The Supreme Court has repeatedly upheld laws that exempt religious beliefs and practices from generally applicable rules against Establishment Clause claims.(see footnote 76) That is all RLPA does. And the Court has never remotely suggested that to preserve religious freedom in more than one area of public policy at the same time is an ''establishment of religion,'' whereas to do so on a statue-by-statute basis is perfectly acceptable.

    Sixth and finally, the separation-of-powers attack on the Act is also weaker than a similar argument that Ms. Hamilton made in Flores—which got no votes there and was recently rejected by the Eighth Circuit in Christians v. Crystal Evangelical Free Church.(see footnote 77) To be sure, Justice Kennedy's majority opinion in Flores discussed separation-of-powers principles, but only in the context of justifying and explaining the Court's interpretation of Section 5.(see footnote 78) The Court did not suggest, much less hold, that RFRA violated the constitutional separation of powers in addition to being beyond Congress's authority under Section 5.(see footnote 79)

    In contrast to RFRA, moreover, the Act does not purport to be a full-blown ''restoration'' by Congress of the rules applicable to free-exercise claims prior to the Supreme Court's decision in Employment Division v. Smith.(see footnote 80) So no one can plausibly claim that Congress in this legislation is somehow trying to second-guess or ''overrule'' the Court as to the proper interpretation of the Constitution in litigated cases. Nor, for the same reason, can anyone plausibly claim that the act is an effort to ''amend the Constitution'' without proper ratification procedures.
 Page 120       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Indeed, by enacting this legislation, Congress is simply taking up the Supreme Court's invitation in Smith to resolve issues of religious freedom through the democratic process. In Smith, the Court characterized its decision as ''leaving [religious] accommodation to the political process,'' and further stated: ''Just as a society that believes in the negative protection accorded to the press by the First Amendment is likely to enact laws that affirmatively foster the dissemination of the printed word, so also a society that believes in the negative protection accorded to religious belief can be expected to be solicitous of that value in its legislation as well.''(see footnote 81) That same invitation was reiterated by Justice Scalia, the author of Smith, in his concurrence in Flores: ''The issue presented by Smith is, quite simply, whether the people, through their elected representatives, or rather this Court, shall control the outcome of [religious accommodation] cases. . . . The historical evidence . . . does nothing to undermine the conclusion we reached in Smith: It shall be the people.''(see footnote 82) Given this explicit invitation in Smith and Flores to the people's elected representatives, it is highly unlikely that the Court would fault Congress for having carried out the will of the people within the sphere of Congress's enumerated powers.

    Finally, with all respect to Professor Eisgruber, the argument that Section 3(a) violates the separation of powers by allocating the burden of proof to defendants on most issues in free exercise cases is frivolous. There is no case-law support for that position. And it is refuted by Supreme Court decisions upholding Congress's power to do just that in constitutional civil-rights cases.(see footnote 83)
 Page 121       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

IS THE ACT A WISE USE OF FEDERAL POWER?

    Now I recognize—and strongly believe—that even if a statute does not exceed Congress's power under existing interpretations of the commerce clause, or Section 5, or whatever provision Congress invokes, it may still be objectionable on federalism grounds as a matter of policy. But this is not such a statute.

    First of all, the Act's impact on the States is carefully limited in key ways. For example, Section 2(d) expressly gives a state or local government great latitude in choosing a remedy for a violation of the statute. The government may not only change the policy that results in a burden on religion; it may also leave the policy in place but grant religious exemptions—or do anything else that eliminates the religious burden. Section 2(c) also prevents the federal government from denying or withholding financial assistance as a remedy for violations. And Section 4(c) greatly reduces the litigation burden on states by subjecting prisoner claims brought under the Act to the Prison Litigation Reform Act of 1995 and subsequent amendments.

    By contrast, as I have already explained, the Act does not ''push the envelope'' of Congressional power. All it does is extend to religious exercise the same types of protections that Congress has traditionally used to protect other values such as non-discrimination.

    And so the fundamental policy issue presented by the Act is this: Is religious freedom as important as the value of non-discrimination, or even other values—such as access to abortion clinics—that have been protected through similar uses of federal power? If not, then perhaps an additional application of the federal commerce power is not worth the price. But if religious freedom is as important as the other values that Congress has protected through similar measures, the Act is a wise and sensible use of that power.
 Page 122       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    For me, other than the rule of law itself, there is no value more deserving of protection than religious liberty. I believe religious liberty is central to God's entire plan of happiness for us, His children.(see footnote 84) And I believe that is one of the principal reasons He inspired our Founding Fathers to organize this nation as they did, and why He has protected it to this day.(see footnote 85) Because of these beliefs, I have no difficulty concluding that the value of religious liberty is at least as important as other values that Congress has previously protected through means similar to those used in the Act. But that is the key issue each Member will have to decide for himself or herself.

WILL THE ACT HELP PROTECT RELIGIOUS LIBERTY?

    This leads me to the final issue: Will the Act actually help protect religious liberty?

    Preliminarily, it is important to remember that the Act is carefully crafted to avoid any unintended, adverse impact on religion. Section 5(e), for example, makes clear that a finding under the Act that a particular religious exercise affects commerce ''does not give rise to any inference or presumption that the religious exercise is subject to any other law regulating commerce.'' Similarly, Section 5(b) precludes any effort to use the Act as a basis for any claims against a religious organization, including a religiously affiliated school or university, whose activities do not rise to the level of ''acting under color of law.'' Under the Supreme Court's decisions, that is a very difficult showing to make.(see footnote 86)
 Page 123       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Nor do I think Section 2(a) would create discrimination in favor of large, mainstream religions and religious groups against smaller or less mainstream groups. The test under Section 2(a) is not whether the particular group has a discernible impact on commerce, but whether the type of religious exercise has such an impact. Thus, the religious practices of a wide range of religious groups could and should be aggregated in determining whether the commerce requirement has been satisfied. This greatly reduces any advantage large religious groups might otherwise enjoy in establishing an impact on interstate commerce.

    Nor do I believe the commerce requirement of Section 2(a) would in any way ''cheapen'' religion, as some have claimed. That provision does not require a claimant to show that his or her religious exercise is a commercial activity. All it requires is some impact on commerce. I think religious people are smart enough to draw a distinction between actions that are themselves commercial, and actions that in the aggregate have an impact on commerce. Thus, I do not believe the Act will in any way harm religious freedom.

    By contrast, each of the three main operative provisions of the Act will materially increase the level of legal protection for religious liberty throughout the nation. First, Section 3(a) will provide a means of redressing a broad range of violations of the Free Exercise Clause that cannot be enforced effectively today because some of the elements of a violation are so difficult to detect and prove. As a litigator, I can tell you that shifting the burden of proof on some of those elements will, by itself, have a powerful, salutary impact on the way in which government bodies respond to actual or potential free-exercise claims.

 Page 124       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    Consider for example a school district that rents its facilities to private users on weekends, but because of hostility to religion, is considering whether to prevent those facilities from being used for worship services. If the school district knows that an adversely affected religious group would have to prove that the district acted with an anti-religious purpose, they may simply agree to adopt the restriction, keep silent about their motivations, and hope for the best. But if they know they will have to prove affirmatively that they acted for legitimate reasons, they will think twice before adopting the restriction. Or at least their lawyers will so advise them.(see footnote 87)

    Second, as will be explained in greater detail by Professor Cole Durham, Section 3(b) will provide a very important institutional benefit to churches and other religious bodies by making it more difficult for local land-use regulators to exclude religious buildings. Few things are more central to most peoples' religious practice than the ability to worship in a nice building, in a nice location, and not too far from one's home.

    Third, by reinstating the ''compelling interest'' test for government decisions falling within Congress's power under the commerce and spending clauses, Section 2 will go some distance toward closing the remaining gap between the level of protection provided for religious freedom prior to Smith and the protection that currently exists. Exactly how far will depend to some extent on how the Supreme Court construes the scope of the commerce power. But even if the Supreme Court significantly narrows its interpretation of that power, Section 2 would still likely protect a great deal of religious activity. At a minimum, religion would be protected under federal law to the same extent as other important values such as non-discrimination. And that is perhaps the most anyone can hope for.
 Page 125       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    At the end of the day, I believe a combination of RFRA and RLPA, supplemented by the Supreme Court's existing interpretation of the Free Exercise Clause, will likely cover about 95 percent of the religious-liberty problems that were covered by the compelling interest test prior to Smith. And that of course means that this patchwork of statutory and constitutional protections will be about 95 percent as effective as a constitutional amendment restoring the compelling interest test in all cases alleging a deprivation of religious freedom. Given the difficulty and uncertainty surrounding any constitutional amendment, I believe it is wise to take a statutory approach again before proposing and submitting a constitutional amendment. With so much at stake, Congress should not let the perfect become the enemy of the good.

    In sum, the proposed Act is plainly constitutional. It is a wise and prudent use of federal power. And it will have an enormous, positive impact on religious freedom in this country. Thank you again for the opportunity to testify on this important subject.

    Mr. CANADY. Mr. Stern.

STATEMENT OF MARC STERN, DIRECTOR, LEGAL DEPARTMENT, AMERICAN JEWISH CONGRESS

    Mr. STERN. I want to thank you for putting me on last. The first time the committee held hearings I spoke after some very eloquent ministers. This time I get to speak after a number of law professors. It is going to be a lot easier to sound interesting this time.
 Page 126       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    I have two tasks today. One is to demonstrate the substantial economic impact of religious activity, and the second is to discuss the impact of RLPA on civil rights laws.

    My grandmother supported herself and my mother during the Great Depression by operating a little kosher chicken market. And the way the business operated was that she would buy chickens from a local wholesaler. Somebody would come in and want to buy a chicken, and my grandmother would arrange for the ritual slaughterer to come in and slaughter the chicken. It was a local business.

    Today the kosher poultry market is dominated by two or three large firms located in Indiana, Pennsylvania, and Iowa, all of which distribute nationally.

    On the desk in front of me are two piles of catalogs. One comes from a Baptist Association, of which there are 1,200 in the United States. One is taken from the shelves of a Baptist church in Virginia. These are catalogs of materials sold to religious organizations, especially designed to meet religious needs. I have from the Catholic Directory, which is the national how-do-you-find-things-in-the-Catholic-Church directory, an advertisement for a Munich firm of stained glass makers, which has its American offices 2 or 3 miles from where I live in New Jersey. Pictured are stained glass windows installed in churches in Covington, Kentucky; Seattle, Washington; Philadelphia, Pennsylvania, and Germany.

    I have as well as catalogs addressed to synagogues. One sells synagogue furniture. The furniture is made in Israel and custom-designed for synagogues across the United States. The other is a catalog of a business that started out 100 years ago on the lower east side selling locally; now does 70 percent of its business nationwide by mail order.
 Page 127       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    The economic impact of religion, of course, is not limited to what churches buy and what they sell. Estimates range between $44 billion and $66 billion a year of charitable donations to houses of worship. When one adds to that the amounts paid in tuition to just the three largest streams of church schools, Catholic schools, about $6.5 billion; $1.2 billion to Christian schools; about half a billion dollars to Jewish schools, (there are yet others that I haven't calculated), when one adds all of that together and then one takes into account hospitals, which operate under church auspices and frequently under church rules that come into conflict with Government regulation—e.g., abortion and end-of-life decision-making. Catholic hospitals are very large networks. They are 10 of the 20 largest HMO networks in the country, and, again, billions of dollars flow through those institutions. They buy and sell things in interstate commerce. They hire people, and those people spend the money they earn, and that has an impact on religious commerce.

    I don't think there can really be any serious question about the extent to which religion is a significant player on the American economic scene. It doesn't mean religion, as Karl Marx might have had it, simply another economic enterprise. It doesn't mean that everything that happens in the name of religion affects interstate commerce. There are lots of small and private religious activities that may have no larger connections. But religion as a whole is clearly a major economic factor.

    I would say two things. In my view, the Commerce Clause question was settled last year by the Supreme Court in the case of Camps Newfound Town of Harrison, in which there was a passive Commerce Clause question. The camp was not tax-exempt under Maine law because many of its campers came from out of Maine. That limitation was challenged as interfering with interstate commerce. And the town, in defense of its tax scheme, said this wasn't commerce at all, campers weren't articles of commerce, and that camps were not in the business of making a profit and therefore could not invoke the Commerce Clause.
 Page 128       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    The Court, in a very short paragraph that I quote in my written testimony, just rejected that out of hand. People move interstate. The camp buys and sells things interstate. That puts it in interstate commerce.

    When you take that small camp and you multiply it across the scope of religion in the United States, it seems to me perfectly clear that Congress is within its authority in using the Commerce Clause here.

    Let me say just quickly on this as well: Congress often uses its Commerce Clause power to protect an industry to allow it to grow, to allow it to function, depending upon the needs of that industry. With regard to the Internet, it may mean exempting Internet commerce from local taxation. With regard to railroads, it means that States can't regulate what size cars or when railroads run. Each industry has its own needs to work as a national player on the economy. What religion needs is deregulation from State control.

    Very briefly about civil rights laws, I would emphasize again what is frequently lost sight of. RLPA is not a statute that by itself trumps any particular practice or statute. It simply says you have got to look at it again and see if the statute or practice meets these standards: Does it serve a very important government interest, and does it do so in a way least burdensome to religion?

    It invalidates no civil rights law or any other law. In that respect, it is much narrower than existing exemptions from civil rights laws that give carte blanche to religious institutions to engage in religious discrimination, which is a typical feature of civil rights laws. Many civil rights laws have broader provisions—apply that same standard to anything a religious institution does.
 Page 129       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    RLPA is not that broad. It gives the government a chance to justify its regulation. As I say in detail in the testimony, there aren't any religious organizations of any significance, and I don't know of any altogether, that practice or encourage racial discrimination. There are very few, and here the picture is a little more cloudy with regard to sexual discrimination. Moreover, it is settled by case law, that outside the area of hiring ministers, the claims of sexual equality are going to prevail over religious exemptions. That is even for religious institutions, to say nothing of for-profit institutions. I don't know of a single for-profit institution that has ever raised a successful religious freedom claim as against a civil rights claim. We can go into later, if there are questions, about how it would apply to marital status discrimination and gay rights discrimination, but I would expect largely that same pattern would hold.

    Why, then, is it necessary to include civil rights laws within the scope of RLPA? There are several answers, one political. Once you start making exceptions, you are going to find it very hard—lots of interest groups, (Professor Hamilton has already listed some of them), are going to come and say, we also have important interests, we ought to be outside the scope of RLPA, and soon we won't have anything worth doing.

    But the second reason particularly relates to gay rights legislation and marital discrimination, marital status discrimination in particular. Those discrimination laws embody a particular view of hotly contested moral issues, issues where we may agree that in public we won't discriminate, but the underlying moral issue is very much in dispute in our society. To say in RLPA that some moral views are outside the universe of polite discourse, we are not even going to allow them to be questioned, is in effect to use RLPA to say that certain religious views ought not to be even heard, ought not to be considered. And given the political controversy and the genuine moral debate over those issues in the country, it seems to me that that would be unwise, particularly since it is unlikely that many people raise those claims and that they will be successful in any number of cases to change our commitment to equal treatment of all citizens, to note these cases out of court from the outset.
 Page 130       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Thank you. I am sorry I ran late.

    Mr. CANADY. Thank you.

    [The prepared statement of Mr. Stern follows:]

PREPARED STATEMENT OF MARC STERN, DIRECTOR, LEGAL DEPARTMENT, AMERICAN JEWISH CONGRESS

    Article I, §8, cl. 3 authorizes Congress to ''regulate Commerce with foreign nations, and among the several States.'' I am not here as an expert on the Commerce Clause. For me to claim such expertise would border on perjury. I rather come to lay out some of the economic facts about religious life in the United States.



    The Commerce Clause is the constitutional hook on which Congress rests its authority to act, not a characterization of the interests involved. City of Boerne teaches that broad religious liberty protection needs to rest on an enumerated power of Congress within the list in Art. I, §8, other than §5 of the Fourteenth Amendment. The Commerce Clause is one such power on which this bill rests, albeit not the only one.

    The use of the Commerce Clause as a hook for legislation whose political and social heart is a moral principle is hardly unprecedented. Some of the nation's most important pieces of social legislation rest on the Commerce Clause. The most visible (and successful) recent examples are Titles II and VII of the 1964 Civil Rights Act, banning racial, sexual and religious discrimination in places of public accommodation and employment. (Earlier still, Congress used this power to ban child labor and the interstate transportation of women for immoral purposes—the Mann Act). No one believes that the principle of non-discrimination embodied in these landmark pieces of legislation is tainted because it rests on the Commerce Clause. The clients I represent who seek religious accommodation in the workplace are not in the slightest offended that the Act upon which their cases is premised rests on the Commerce Clause. Those to be protected by the Religious Liberty Protection Act will no doubt also not be offended that their rights are protected by the Commerce Clause.
 Page 131       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

II

    We know authoritatively that many activities of religious not-for-profit corporations come within the Commerce Clause. The Supreme Court told us so last Term in Camps Newfound/Owatanna v. Town of Harrison, 117 S.Ct. 1590 (1997). The summer camps were religious, operated by Christian Scientists, to allow children to grow ''spiritually and physically in accordance with the tenets of their religion.'' Id. at 1594. It challenged (ultimately, successfully) a preference in the operation of a real property tax exemption for camps serving Maine residents primarily as a violation of the Commerce Clause.

    At the outset, this claim was met with the twin objections that campers were not articles of commerce, and that the camps were not in the business of making a profit, and hence that the camps could not raise a Commerce Clause challenge. The Court rejected these defenses:

  Even though petitioner's camp does not make a profit, it is unquestionably engaged in commerce, not only as a purchaser, see Katzenbach v. McClung, 379 U.S. 294, 300–301 (1964); United States v. Lopez, 514 U.S. 549 (1995), but also as a provider of goods and services. It markets those services, together with an opportunity to enjoy the natural beauty of an inland lake in Maine, to campers who are attracted to its facility from all parts of the Nation.

Id. at 1596.
 Page 132       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Moreover, as we will show, the very size of an action can bring it within the Commerce Clause if it affects interstate commerce. NLRB v. Fainblatt, 306 U.S. 601 (1939); Wickert v. Fillburn, cited in Hodel v. Virginia Surface Mining Assn., 452 U.S. 264, 308 (1981). In that case, Justice Rehnquist insisted upon a substantial effect on interstate commerce, id. At 310–11. Accord Lopez v. U.S., 115 S.Ct. 1624, 1630 (1994). ''Where economic activity substantially affects interstate commerce, legislation regulating that activity will be sustained.'' Lopez also reaffirms Wickert's holding that the cumulative effects of small-scale economic activity can bring an activity within the Commerce Clause.

    Much religious activity will fall within these rules. Although, perhaps contra to Karl Marx, religion is not primarily an economic activity, in all its various forms, institutional and personal, it surely has a substantial effect on commerce.

    A caveat before I turn to the statistics. As a consequence of the American tradition that religion is not the business of government, the government appears to have relatively little relevant data. Churches are not required to file the informational return required of other not-for-profits (Form 990). The Census Bureau asks no questions about religious affiliations, nor, as best as I can discover, does it survey churches to assay their economic activity. The Department of Housing and Urban Development does a biennial survey of housing, and inquires into those factors which lead people to select a home, but it asks no questions about religion. (I.e., whether the presence of a church makes a difference. Is the presence of a significant body of fellow believers a prerequisite for moving into a community?) The Commerce Department does keep figures on religious construction, but these may well substantially underestimate the extent of that activity.
 Page 133       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    As I will discuss, there are private studies by Independent Sector and others, notably the National Association of Fund Raising Counsel and Empty Tomb, which attempt to quantify the extent of philanthropic activity directed toward the support of religious activity. These data are imprecise in part because no government agency collects official data. Moreover, there are religious institutions involved in a variety of activities likely to come within the scope of RLPA which are not houses of worship, and are lumped together with other apparently secular categories. On the other hand, the possibility of some dual reporting cannot be eliminated, either. Still, the numbers I describe are the ones that experts and others in the field point to with some regularity, and in some measure, cross-check with each other.

    Most churches and religious not-for-profit organizations support themselves with membership dues and fees for services. Independent Sector's 1990 survey(see footnote 88) reports that 60 percent of national household charitable giving totaling 122.5 billion dollars(see footnote 89) was given to religious institutions, or a total of 65.76 billion dollars. More recently some have argued that the amount of religious giving is exaggerated by some 20 percent, and that the total of giving to churches is only (!) 44 billion dollars.(see footnote 90) The Not-for-Profit Almanac (1996–7), p.175 reports that revenues for religious institutions in 1992–93 were 58.3 million dollars. The Almanac also reports that religious congregations had current operating expenditures of 41 billion dollars. Some of the difference is no doubt savings or reserves, but much of the rest is no doubt spent on capital improvements—new buildings and upgrading old ones, a fact which makes RLPA's zoning provisions quite important. To the extent that localities interfere with the ability of religious institutions to build, they reduce the amount of commerce in construction—much of which involves the interstate movement of goods (stained glass, furnishings) and services.
 Page 134       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Even as to houses of worship these figures on philanthropy understate the impact of houses of worship—themselves only a subset of the religious community. According to the Almanac, income from endowments (for 1992) is another 1.3 billion dollars. In 1992,some 6 billion dollars was spent on capital improvements and new construction (Almanac, p. 190, Table 4.2), up from 4.8 billion dollars in 1987. (By comparison, all educational institutions—a category which includes many religious institutions, the figures were 6.4 and 4.9 billion dollars respectively.) In 1982, religious institutions had endowment investment income of 1 billion dollars, and spent $800,000,000 on construction. In short, in recent years there has been a substantial leap in the amount of capital construction by religious organizations.

    These figures include only current financial expenditures. Even more capital is invested in religious institutions in the form of real property and buildings, some of which have been dedicated to church use for centuries. Recent studies indicate that these facilities are used by other community groups, often at reduced rents; this multiplies their effect both on the economy and the well-being of our communities and the nation.

    Data, however, is hard to come by. In almost all states, statistics on exempt property are maintained locally, not at the state level. I have not had the resources to compile this data piecemeal. Two states, however, do maintain such data: New York and Wisconsin.

    The most recent figures for New York show 13.5 billion dollars of property (In some 23,000 parcels) held as houses of worship, and an additional 3.6 billion dollars of parsonages. Other property used by religious organizations (cemeteries, schools, hospitals, and the like) are not broken out separately. This amounts to about 5 percent of the total exempt property (a category which includes government buildings and public parks).(see footnote 91)
 Page 135       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    The most recent figures for Wisconsin (1996) show that church/religious property amounts to almost $5 billion of tax exempt property, which constitutes 40.6% of all exempt private real property.(see footnote 92) As in the case of New York, other property used by religious organizations are not broken out separately.

    Houses of worship do not exhaust the economic extent of religious activity. At this point, though, certainty becomes even less possible. Religious enterprises include schools, hospitals, and social welfare institutions. Some of the latter two categories may be largely indistinguishable from their secular counterparts, but surely not all. Catholic and Baptist hospitals operate under a series of religious directives. These have in the past clashed with various regulations. Given the consolidation in the health care industry, it is likely that there will be more such clashes. In any event, these hospitals are a significant economic player.

    The Catholic health care sector has a huge economic impact. There are 625 Catholic hospitals in 48 states; 713 long-term care facilities, and 51 HMO's in 32 states. They make up 16 percent of the total U.S. community hospital admissions and outpatient visits. They produce over $44 billion in hospital revenues, much of which is spent, obviously , in interstate commerce in pharmaceutical and other supplies. The assets of these facilities also exceed 44 billion dollars.(see footnote 93) Catholic health care systems account for 10 of the 20 largest health care systems in the country.(see footnote 94) These figures do not, of course, include the large Baptist, Jewish and other religiously affiliated hospitals.

 Page 136       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    The economics of parochial schools are somewhat different than for houses of worship. To varying degrees, depending largely on the vagaries of each denomination's organization, these institutions derive much support from tuition. Catholic schools enroll (according to the National Catholic Education Association) during the most recent school year for which figures are available—1997–98—some 2.5 million students, in 8,200 schools at an average per pupil cost of $2,414, for a rough total of 6.24 billion dollars.

    Conservative Christian schools, according to the National Center for Educational Statistics (March 1998) enroll about a half million students in 3,300 schools. Some 172,000 Jewish students attend some 688 schools. I have been unable to locate average costs for the Christian schools supplying. Applying the Catholic schools' costs to these students, gives a (conservative) total of 1.2 billion dollars.

    Jewish schools are more expensive. The Avi Chai Foundation(see footnote 95) did a study of Jewish schools outside the New York area concerning the 1995–96 school year and non-New York Metropolitan area schools calculated an average cost of between $5,000 and $6,000 per student. Using the lower figure for the entire student population including those in schools in the New York area, we conclude that the tuition costs are $860,000,000. These three streams—and they by far do not exhaust the spectrum—lead to a total of tuition costs of 8.3 billion dollars. These numbers (admittedly rough) do not include fees and charitable contributions, as well as endowment income to the schools, which educate together three-fifths of all non-public school students.

    Some of the funds go to salaries; others go to textbook publishers and computer manufacturers, and sellers of school supplies, all of whom are regularly involved in interstate commerce. These institutions build and maintain buildings with supplies purchased in interstate commerce by companies which are nationwide in scope. The number of buildings (over 12,000) is itself so substantial as to necessarily have an impact on interstate commerce.
 Page 137       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    These figures include only elementary and secondary schools. But religious education does not stop there. Institutions of religious higher education also exist. I do not have figures for the economic impact of the many colleges under religious auspices, even if defined to mean school where religion plays a significant and more than a nominal role in the life of the school, but also in schools of theology. The Association of Theological Schools, representing mainline Protestant schools of theology, represents some 220 schools, enrolling some 65,000 students in the 1996–97 school year at an average cost to student of $6,200 per student for a total of $406,000,000.(see footnote 96) Again, this figure would not include grants or endowment income. And it says nothing of Catholic seminaries, smaller Bible schools, or yeshivot (rabbinical schools).

    Nor is it beyond the realm of the possible that these schools—and hence interstate commerce—would be affected by state imposed substantial burdens. During the 1980's state regulators and operators of so-called Christian schools frequently clashed. In Nebraska, where courts had upheld the broad power of regulation, many schools singly closed their doors rather than operate in violation of their religious principles. Those closures reduced purchases in interstate commerce.

    Another area not included until now is that of charitable giving under religious auspices. The Chronicle of Philanthropy(see footnote 97) annually lists the top 400 charities in the United States. The largest charity in the United States is the Salvation Army, with an annual income of over 2 billion dollars—and it has on several occasions clashed with the government over religious liberty and government regulation. Number 5 is Catholic charities at 1.1 billion dollars. Numbers 7 and 8 were also religious affiliates—the YMCA and Habitat for Humanity. Number 19 at one quarter of a billion dollars is Campus Crusade for Life. Many other religious charities—not individual houses of worship—are scattered through this list.
 Page 138       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    So far what has been said relates to income and capital expenditures of religious institutions. Religious life also has a personal side, one which commands expenditure of funds by believers in furtherance of their religious beliefs and practices, from ritual object to ritually acceptable food to books, music and mass media. Much of these move in either international or interstate commerce.

    The Christian Bookseller Association is the trade association of Christian product suppliers. It has 12,500 member stores in the U.S. selling books, records, apparel and videos. It estimates that it members do 3 billion dollars of annual business, with many stores doing over 1 million dollars a year in annual business. In 1997, it had a convention in Georgia, attended by over 13,000 people, and over 400 exhibitors from across the country and the world.

    The Catholic and Jewish communities also have their own publishers and distributors of religious articles, including furnishings for synagogues and ritual objects. Increasing, these businesses work not as small local bookstores, but as catalog sales business selling objects made in various state and foreign locations across the United States. One such seller to the Jewish market, J. Levine Booksellers, started out as a small bookstore on New York's lower east side 90 years ago. Today, it does 70 percent of its business ($2.5 million) in national mail order business.

    Other enterprises sell church and synagogue furniture by mail order catalog to houses of worship nationwide, as can be seen in particular from the ads in the Catholic Directory. Copies of these will be entered in the record.

 Page 139       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    Some faiths have ritual diet requirements, and these, too, have a substantial impact on interstate commerce, and these, too, have been involved in questions of religious liberty.

    Dr. Joseph Regenstein, a expert on ethnic and religious diets at Cornell University, estimates that there are between 2 and 3 billion dollars in directed sales of kosher food, that is, sales of items where the consumer seeks out a kosher product. A total of some 35 billion dollars of food products are sold which are under rabbinical supervision. A total of 41,000 products are under rabbinical supervision. Grappa to Scones, New York Times, 12/3/97. I can speak here with personal expertise. These foods are available nationally, and their availability in the national market in ordinary groceries and supermarkets has greatly facilitated travel and business by those like myself who observe the kosher food laws. And by the same token, the transition to a national market in Kosher food has greatly simplified the life of those who in pursuit of economic advantage seek to move away for the largest Jewish communities. Kosher food is now more less available everywhere. One large producer, Manishewitz, distributes its products to more than 18,000 supermarkets (out of a national total of 30,000 stores).

    This development has had important implications for the kosher food industry. In Schacter v. U.S., 295 U.S. 495 (1935), the so-called sick chicken case, the Supreme Court invalidated the National Industrial Recovery Act at the behest of a small wholesaler of kosher chickens who purchased some live chickens from other states, but who slaughtered, dressed and sold the chickens for the local market. That was the typical pattern in that era—and again I speak from personal experience because my grandmother (coincidentally named Schacter—the name means ritual slaughterer)owned a small poultry store at the time.

 Page 140       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    Today, the industry is different as is Commerce Clause doctrine. Almost no poultry is ritually slaughtered at the point of sale. Most is slaughtered and prepared by a few large companies. Hebrew National (owned by Conagra), Empire (located in Mifflintown, PA) and Rubashkin (Agra-processor located in Pottsville, Iowa). These companies distribute their products nationally—as a trip to almost any supermarket will disclose. The same pattern holds for beef with Hebrew National, Sinai/48 (owned by Sara Lee) and Rubashkin increasingly dominating the market and pushing out of business small local sellers—in just the way small hardware stores have yielded to large national chains like Home Depot.

    The Muslim community too, has some dietary restrictions, notably with regard to the slaughter of beef and the avoidance of pork. It has three or four supervising agencies (there are some 80 or 90 Jewish agencies, but only 4 national ones), one of the biggest of which is the Islamic Food and Nutrition Board of America located in Illinois. Much of the work of the councils involves certifying the export of American products for the overseas Islamic market.

    There is a domestic market as well. I spoke to the manager of the largest Hallal market in the Washington area, Hallalco in Falls Church. Hallalco does its own slaughtering. Much of its work involves the slaughter of local beef within Virginia, but when the supply of local beef is insufficient, Hallalco imports live animals for slaughter from Texas. It has now began slaughtering operations in Maryland. It does not produce its own Hallal delicatessen. These it imports from a Hallal producer in Iowa.

    What has been said does not begin to exhaust the extent of the economic impact of churches on interstate commerce. I have not discussed religious broadcasting, nor the many large religious conventions. Does anyone think that Salt Lake City welcomed the Southern Baptists because of their desire to proselytize Mormons? Religious conventions, like other conventions make a real economic contribution to a community. Multiply that by all the conventions held yearly, to say nothing of large revivals, and again the cumulative impact on the national economy is substantial. Add to that the funding that flows from around the country to national and international affiliates or parents of the local religious organization, and one again confronts an important factor on the national economy. I am sure that economists could tell you how that sum multiplies through the economy. Even without it, the impact of religion on the economy is significant to allow Congress, should it choose to do so, to protect this segment of the economy.(see footnote 98)
 Page 141       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

III

    The simple fact is that the Commerce Clause has frequently been applied to religious activities, Camp Newfound, cited earlier, unequivocally establishes that religious institutions can claim the protection of the Commerce Clause even though they are not in the business of making money. Presumably, if such institutions can claim the benefit of the dormant Commerce Clause, whose existence is disputed by some Justices of the Supreme Court, it would seem to follow that Congress can invoke the Clause as an affirmative grant of power to protect the viability of this sector of the economy.

    It would be particularly odd if this were not the case because the courts, including the Supreme Court have routinely applied Commerce Clause legislation to church activities. Thus, in Tony and Susan Alamo Foundation v. United States, 471 U.S. 290 (1985), the Court upheld the minimum wage provisions of the Fair Labor Standards Act to businesses which were part of a church's ministry. In NLRB v. Hanna Boys Center, 940 F.2d 1295 (5th Cir. 1991), the Court upheld the application of the National Labor Relations Act to the non-teaching staff of a religious home.

    Courts have upheld application of various Commerce Clause anti-discrimination laws to various religious institutions. See, e.g., Lukasewski v. Nazareth Hospital, 764 F.Supp. 57 (E.D. Pa. 1991) (age); EEOC v. Southwestern Seminary, 651 F.2d 277 (5th Cir. 198) (religious, racial and gender discrimination); Brock v. Wendell's Woodwork, Inc. 867 F.2d 196 (4th Cir.1989) (child labor).
 Page 142       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    One could multiply examples. Religious broadcasting, itself a multi-billion dollar enterprise, is subject to the Federal Communication Commission's regulations, again based on the Commerce Clause, in the same way that secular broadcasters are. Ritual slaughter is subject to the federal Humane Slaughter Act, and the processing of kosher food is subject to the FDA supervision, all under the Commerce Clause. It is, it seems to me, hard to sustain the proposition that religion is commerce for purposes of regulations which may limit its reach, but it is not commerce when it come to legislation which allows it to flourish.

    Congress frequently has utilized its power under the Commerce Clause to foster business which operates interstate. Sometimes this requires the limitation of the power of states to tax, a power Congress is considering exercising with regard to the Internet. Sometimes it provides that national rules for the operation of an industry preempt local regulation, notably in the case of transportation. No one could run a railroad if each state could regulate the times of operation, and the types of equipment which could be utilized. Congress long ago exercised its power to protect interstate commerce by preempting contrary state regulations.

    Religious enterprise depends on the ability of citizens to exercise free religious choice, not only to the bare holding of beliefs, but to putting them in practice. An important segment of interstate commerce would evaporate if states decide to ban ritual slaughter as inhumane, as several European countries do. Municipalities that ban religious structures altogether restrict commerce in services and materials designed for the church market. If Congress can protect the Internet by barring state laws which would interfere with its functioning, such as taxes and libel laws, why can it not protect the practice of religion which also has an impact on the economy? I think there is no relevant distinction.
 Page 143       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

IV

    I have also been asked to address the question of the impact of the Religious Liberty Protection Act on the civil rights laws. This question has arisen not only in regard to RLPA, but with regard to state religious freedom statutes. Probably no question surrounding RLPA has been discussed with greater passion than this one.

    Let me note first that many civil rights acts already contain substantial exemptions for religious institutions. Thus, Title VII of the 1964 Act allows religious corporations to engage in religious discrimination without restriction. At least as to not-for-profit corporations, this provision is constitutional even as to positions with no religious content. Corporation of the Presiding Bishop v. Amos, 483 U.S. 327 (1987); Killinger v. Sanford University,, 113 F.3d 196 (9th cir. 1997). In Amos, the Court left open the question of whether the exemption applied to for-profit corporations and whether if so applied it was constitutional. Justice Brennan indicated that he thought such application unconstitutional. Title VIII allows religious corporations to engage in religious discrimination in the operation of housing owned by them. New York State's Human Rights law allows religious organizations the right to engage in any form of discrimination if necessary to further its religious purposes. (The exact scope of the exemption is unclear. The one case to reach the New York Court of Appeals gave the section a narrow reading—Schacter v. St. Johns University, 84 N.Y.2d 120 (1993).) The proposed federal gay rights legislation (ENDA) has a broad exemption for not-for-profit organizations, negotiated by gay rights groups and religious organizations, at least some of whom could not support the legislation without such an exemption, but could support it with it.
 Page 144       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    In addition to these statutory exemptions, courts have uniformly refused to intervene the decision of a church to hire or fire ministers, even where there are allegations of racial or secular discrimination outside the scope of the statutory exemptions.

    The federal statutory exemptions are both narrower and broader than RLPA would be. They are narrower in that they generally apply only to religious discrimination by religious corporations, and RLPA would in theory apply to all forms of discrimination by religious institutions and religious individuals. The statutory exemptions are broader—and the significance of the point cannot be overestimated—because they are total and absolute. No matter how important the interest in eliminating a particular form of discrimination, an organization exempt under the statute wins. Not so under RLPA. A person or institution claiming under RLPA must overcome the government's showing of compelling interests—experience indicated that the barrier will frequently be insurmountable.

    How great is the likelihood that RLPA would be used to frustrate the important policies behind the civil rights acts question that should be addressed before one discusses whether RLPA should or should not reach these statutes. Based on past experience in the years predating Employment Division v. Smith, 494 U.S. 872 (1990) the answer as to race is clear—not likely at all. Bans on sexual discrimination will survive RPLA analysis most of the time. There is not much case law for other forms of discrimination, although we have some indications for marital status. There has been a fair amount of litigation as regards marital discrimination, but almost none with regard to sexual orientation discrimination.

 Page 145       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    The leading case with regard to racial discrimination is Bob Jones University v. Simon, 461 U.S. 574 (1983). There a religious university lost its tax exemption because it enforced a ban on inter-racial dating. The University challenged the decision on, inter alia, the grounds that it denied it the Free Exercise of religion. The argument merited only a footnote, in which the Court easily found a compelling interest. I do not know of a single subsequent case in which the claim was advanced that racial discrimination was religiously based and hence immune from regulation. If made, I have no doubt that it would be rejected.

    Claims of sexual discrimination in employment are more frequent. Typically, the cases have arisen in the context employment by a religious organization, there being to the best of my knowledge no claim by a private for-profit employer that his or her religion required discrimination against women, and certainly no such claim has ever been—nor is it likely that one ever would be—upheld. This is not surprising, given the general tendency of the law to equate sexual discrimination with racial discrimination. Title VII's exemption for religious institutions is inapplicable because it deals only with religious discrimination.

    A typical case is EEOC v. Pacific Press, 676 F.2d 1272 (9th Cir. 1980), involving the publication arm of a church. On the grounds that women should not be heads of households, Pacific Press paid women workers less than men. It offered a religious liberty defense, roundly rejected by the Ninth Circuit.

    Less even in results are cases involving parochial school teachers. A typical case involves the single female teacher who becomes pregnant out of wedlock. The school claims such teachers are ''ministers'' and that it can insist that ministers set a moral example. The response typically is that the school does not enforce a similar rule as to male teachers who have sex out of wedlock. The case law is divided on this subject. See, e.g., Dolter v. Wahlert H.S., 483 F.Supp. 266 (N.D. Iowa 1980). The Supreme Court once considered a slight variation on this theme. A parochial school refused to allow mothers (but not fathers) of young children to teach because it believed mothers should be home with their children. The state claimed a compelling interest in ending such sexual role casting, no doubt an important and impelling interest, but which in this case came perilously close to amounting to the suppression of a religious idea. See Hurley v. Boston Gay & Lesbian & Bisexual Group, 515 U.S. 587 (1995). The Supreme Court decided the case on procedural grounds. Ohio Civil Rights Comm'n v. Dayton Christian, 477 U.S. 619 (1986). The case subsequently settled.
 Page 146       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    These cases are typically outside statutory exemptions because they involve sexual, not religious discrimination. At least in the context of the parochial school teachers, they also come close to the rule of non-interference in the selection of ministers. On the other hand, they also expose children to sexual stereotypes which the state surely does not wish to see perpetuated. In short, these are hard cases and do not for me admit of across the board answers. And, indeed, the courts have not given uniform answers, differing both on their statements of the legal balance to be struck and on their evaluations of the specific facts observed in each case. RLPA would not change this result.

    What can be said with certainty about these cases are the following propositions:

(1) claims for outright race and sex discrimination outside the ministerial or teaching professions are almost certain to be rejected;

(2) for-profit employees, and by extension private persons under the statutes (i.e., public accommodation laws) will not be heard to successfully argue that RLPA exempts them from civil rights law compliance;

(3) when the compelling interest test was the law, i.e., before Employment Division v. Smith, the free exercise defense was rarely made successfully with regard to sex discrimination, and never with regard to racial discrimination;

(4) the cases where a free exercise claim was given serious consideration involved substantial and conflicting values, which should not be summarily and broadly decided; and
 Page 147       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

(5) the existence of the ability to raise such claims, sometimes even successfully, did not in any substantial way impede national progress toward reducing the general incidence of illicit and invidious discrimination.

    I know of no denomination that purports to regard racial discrimination as a religious duty. Most, if not all, regard it as a heinous sin. And while there still is substantial disagreement over sex roles, I am unaware of any church or religious organization which encourages its followers to discriminate against women in the private workplace. These facts do not eliminate the possibility of a religiously based claim to practice discrimination in the workplace, but they greatly reduce its likelihood.(see footnote 99)

    The hardest questions involve relatively new civil rights—those of marital status and sexual orientation. As to the latter, there has been as yet relatively little litigation, in part because these statutes tend to exempt religious organizations. This is the case by terms of New York City's ''gay rights'' law, and presumably most other gay ''rights'' laws because they fit into the general framework of human rights laws which have such exemption. In the case of New Jersey, where the legislation seemed (at least to one church) unclear on whether the ban on sexual orientation discrimination would apply to its hiring of youth ministers and the like (perhaps because the statute exempted only religious discrimination by religious groups). After lengthy procedural battles, the state conceded that the statute would not apply to such decisions in keeping with the general rule that courts will not police the hiring of ministers. These exemptions for religious organization would continue under the proposed ENDA. Thus, to the extent that RLPA would be invoked by religious organizations would break no new ground, and change nothing.
 Page 148       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    RLPA would be available to private parties seeking to avoid ''sexual orientation'' discrimination. Such challenges were available under RFRA, and none seem to have been brought. The closest case is one involving the discharge of a public official who criticized homosexuals. The court found that the state had a compelling interest in ensuring an end to sexual orientation legislation, sufficient to justify discharge of the official. Lumpkin v. Brown, 109 F.3d 1498 (9th Cir. 1997). While not dispositive, perhaps, of the rights of private parties, I think the decision is indicative of the likely result—that an end to discrimination of the basis of sexual orientation furthers a compelling interest.

    Case law on the question of claims for exemption from bans on marital status discrimination are mixed. Alaska, in Swanner v. Anchorage Equal Right Comm'n, 874 P.2d 274 (1994). California reached the same result, but by different (and quite questionable) reasoning in Smith v. FEHC, 12 Cal.4th 1143 (1996). Massachusetts, however held in Attorney General of Massachusetts v. Desilets, XXX Mass. XXX (1994), that a private landlord was entitled under the state constitution to prove that the state's interest in making housing available for cohabitating couples was not seriously compromised by allowing a small landlord with religious exemptions to such rentals not to do so. Illinois and Minnesota have each had similar cases, but neither resulted in an opinion on the issue confronting the Committee today.

    Against this background, it can be said that the courts have not rushed to allow religious freedom claims to trump civil rights claims. With regard to marital status, where we have more litigation, the most that can be gotten from the only decision to (partially) favor a religious landlord is that she or he might be exempt if their personal refusal to rent to unmarried couples will not significantly affect their chance for finding housing and only in such circumstances will such a claim succeed.
 Page 149       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Now it is fairly debatable whether the purpose of the ban on marital status discrimination is only or primarily to ensure the availability of housing—or if it is also to prevent the psychological and social stigma caused by such discrimination, in which case it may be wrong. Either way, however, the practical effects of following Desilets would still be, in practical terms, very small. Surely no large, or even mid-sized commercial landlord would be able to use RLPA to avoid compliance with an anti-marital status discrimination ordinance.

    Understandably, precisely because there is in our society an ongoing moral debate about the wisdom and morality of granting unmarried couples and gay and lesbian couples equal rights with traditional heterosexual married couples, those who favor equal rights for these groups—as my organization does—are reluctant to countenance exemptions because they may be seen as encouraging wide-spread evasion of the newly adopted legal norms against discrimination.

    I understand the argument, but am not persuaded that it is so powerful that it ought to foreclose inquiry into whether the state's interest is sufficiently important to outweigh the burden on religious practice.

    First, given the importance of egalitarianism in our political and legal culture, it seems unlikely that allowing the inquiry will result in any wide-scale sanctioning of invidious discrimination. Second, there are cases nominally within the scope of the anti-discrimination laws where exemption is certainly appropriate, such as the case of the pro-life printer sued under the public accommodation law for refusing to print pro-choice flyers, or the Catholic church sued for refusing to rent a parish hall to one of its theological critics. Exempting civil rights from RLPA would leave these cases untouched. Third, in the analogous area of clashes between the freedom of association and the rights to be free of discrimination, the Supreme Court, applying compelling interest analysis, has refused to follow a per se rule, preferring instead a case-by-case adjudication. Compare Roberts v. U.S. Jaycees, 468 U.S. 609 (1984) with Hurley v. Irish-American Gay & Lesbian & Bisexual Group, 515 U.S. 587 (1995). No reason appears why the right of religious practice should not be treated the same way. Fourth, it bears repeating again, that RLPA does not command blind deference to religious objections to complying with the civil rights laws, or any other law. It compels only a second look; a weighing of competing interests. RLPA does not cut a wide swathe through the civil rights laws.
 Page 150       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Allowing religious claims to be heard accords those who hold them a level of moral respect and seriousness which in my experience greatly facilitates acceptance of any ultimate judgment compelling compliance with the civil rights laws. That alone would be an important reason not to exempt civil rights laws from RLPA's reach.

    A second reason is political. Consider ENDA. Would its chances of passage be enhanced or reduced if religious believers thought it would apply to youth ministers or Sunday school teachers, or church day care? RLPA goes even less far—because it is not a blanket exemption, but only a second look—but it does make legislation in many controversial areas more palatable to religious believers of both left and right. And excluding civil rights laws from RLPA would simply fuel endless calls from supporters of this or that cause to place their cause beyond question.

    The third reason is, I think, most important. On issues such as marital status and sexual orientation there are profound moral differences in this society. Those moral debates are serious, weighty and unresolved. Exempting civil rights claims from RLPA amounts to a declaration that some principles are beyond serious question, are not, in fact, morally serious. At least with regard to marital status and sexual orientation that is surely not factually accurate, whatever view one ultimately takes on both the underlying moral issue or the narrower question of how a RLPA claim should be resolved. (It may be true with regard to race, but as to such claims there is only a slightly greater than zero chance that such a claim would prevail.) So declaring would alienate many morally decent individuals, relegating their most deeply held moral beliefs to beyond the pale.

 Page 151       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    If there were a serious danger that even considering the claim for exemption would threaten this nation's fundamental egalitarian commitment, there might be reason to exempt civil rights laws from RLPA. But in my judgment, that is not the case. I recognize that discrimination still exists, and its victims are understandably reluctant to tolerate any questioning of their right to equal treatment. But in my judgment, it is not the case. The commitment to equal treatment is too well settled , too broadly and deeply held, to be shaken because in some few instances we allow those with profound moral objections to particular policies to question these egalitarian values, and perhaps in some even smaller number of cases, exempt themselves from them. To do so is simply to acknowledge that our society honors numerous values, equal treatment being one, and religious liberty another, and we must, if at all possible, do our best to honor both.

    Mr. CANADY. Mr. Scott.

    Mr. SCOTT. Mr. Chairman, part of my concern about the constitutionality of this bill stems from some of the language in Boerne, where the Court expresses almost a hostility to this kind of legislation and gives me the idea that it won't take much for them to throw out the next one. And the language that I am referring to says in governments—where they stated in the Smith—where they remind in Boerne what they said in the Smith case, which says, government's ability to enforce generally applicable prohibitions of socially harmful conduct cannot depend on measuring the effects of governmental action on a religious objector's spiritual development. To make an individual's obligation to obey such law contingent upon the law's coincidence with his religious beliefs, except where the State's interest is compelling, contradicts both constitutional tradition and common sense.
 Page 152       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    That kind of suggests that if they find something to throw this out with, it just suggests to me that they are going to.

    Much has been said today about the Commerce Clause and how we can do this under the Commerce Clause. I have a couple of questions, particularly since comparisons have been made to the civil rights laws. I just throw it out to whoever wants to comment.

    Didn't the Court in Boerne specifically go out of its way to show how the civil rights laws were different in that there was a much stronger record and that the laws were narrowly tailored to address the problem, whereas RFRA was a broad, kind of unfocused law that covered a lot more and a lot—frankly a lot of out of proportion to whatever the law was? Does somebody want to comment?

    Ms. HAMILTON. Representative Scott, I would be happy to talk about that. That actually is precisely in the opinion, and it was in our briefs as well. It was clear from the beginning to me that the problem with RFRA was that it was an unfocused attempt to exert congressional power. This bill seems to have the same problem, that it is a scattershot approach attempting to embrace as much religious conduct as possible without examining the particular Federal interest that is or could be implicated. I think you are right to say that there is a high degree of risk that the Supreme Court would invalidate RLPA rather quickly.

    Mr. EISGRUBER. May I also speak to that?

    Congressman Scott, I agree with your interpretation of the Court's opinion in Flores, and I think it points to an important aspect of the remarks that have been offered in defense of RLPA today, wherein an effort has been made to assimilate this statute to an antidiscrimination statute.
 Page 153       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    From a constitutional perspective, it is easy to understand why people would want to invoke the authority of the antidiscrimination laws. Obviously they have done wonderful things. And in addition, the Court in Boerne was quite clear about the existence of constitutional authority to enact those laws.

    As I said in my earlier remarks, I think that authority extends to any law that would be reasonably understandable as an effort to protect against discrimination on the basis of religious interests. There is no reason that this should be construed as an authority that Congress has only with respect to some forms of discrimination and not others. On the other hand, RLPA is not plausibly construed as an antidiscrimination statute.

    Let me give an example of the kind of law that would come under scrutiny under the zoning provisions of RLPA which I think cannot be justified in terms of an antidiscrimination theory. There are some cities which have greenbelt ordinances, zoning restrictions around the city designed to preserve open space. These greenbelt ordinances prevent any kind of building from taking place in those open spaces. It may well be cheaper to build in those open spaces. Some of that land may be farmland, and if you have got a greenbelt around a city that is filling up, the land outside of the city may well be less expensive to purchase. But those restrictions are going to operate on any enterprise that wants to build there, on anybody who wants to build there regardless of how charitable or salutary their motives are.

    As I understand the land use section of this bill, it creates, as Mr. Schaerr said earlier, something like the compelling interest test that would have to be satisfied in order to apply that kind of ordinance to a church which sought to construct in that area simply for the reason that it would be cheaper to do so.
 Page 154       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    That kind of a law goes much further than anything plausibly construed as an antidiscrimination statute, and I think this law for that reason will be unable to claim the benefits of the Court's doctrine on antidiscrimination laws.

    Mr. LAYCOCK. Can I speak to that question?

    Mr. CANADY. The gentleman's time has expired. Without objection, the gentlemen will have 5 additional minutes.

    Mr. SCOTT. Thank you, Mr. Chairman.

    Mr. LAYCOCK. Mr. Scott, I think you are right that the Court is hostile to the protection of religious liberty, but I don't think we should infer from that that it will run amuck with Commerce Clause doctrine and Spending Clause doctrine to implement that hostility and strike down legislation that presents questions that are very different from the constitutional questions presented in Boerne.

    Everything in the Boerne case is in the context of whether RFRA was an act to enforce the Fourteenth Amendment. And the Court said, in order for it to be an act to enforce the Fourteenth Amendment, it has to be an act to enforce the Fourteenth Amendment as interpreted in the Smith case.

    So all the talk about proportionality and connection and whether there is discrimination was in the context of whether there was sufficient evidence of widespread violations of the free exercise clause as the Court interpreted it in Smith.
 Page 155       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Mr. SCOTT. You are talking about that entire analysis with the Commerce Clause? They went through it with the section 5, and now we have to go through the same thing as to whether or not a law that the Supreme Court is expressing hostility to—I mean, you had five or six votes to begin with, and then another one said, well, you are establishing a religion, so I don't have to hear any more. I mean, you have got some that are extremely hostile to this idea. So in your commerce evaluation, wouldn't you have to assume that they are going to be as restrictive as possible in that analysis?

    Mr. LAYCOCK. They may interpret the connection to commerce more narrowly here than they do in other contexts, and that will have the consequence that the bill doesn't cover as much as we might like it to cover. But the point I was trying to make is that when they say in Boerne that there is no sufficient showing here that this bill protects against constitutional violations, this is simply a question that is not relevant under the Spending Clause and Commerce Clause provisions. They are not worried about the Spending or Commerce Clause anywhere in the Boerne opinion, and they couldn't have been. It would have been utterly irrelevant. And when they say the civil rights cases are different—first of all, it was the Voting Rights Act of 1965 that they said in some detail was different, but again, it is in the context of whether there was a showing of a constitutional violation. There is not a word in Boerne that suggests that the commerce power to protect against racial discrimination is any different from the use of the commerce power to project religious liberty. That issue simply was not presented.

    Mr. SCOTT. Well, when you are talking about the Commerce Clause, if the—I think Mr. Stern has shown that churches obviously are involved in commerce. Does the law, if you are going to use the Commerce Clause, have to affect commerce, or does it just have to deal with an entity in commerce?
 Page 156       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Obviously, the civil rights laws, when you are using the Commerce Clause, have an effect on how commerce is going to take place. And we have had testimony today that this bill, whatever effect it may have, will not affect commerce.

    Mr. STERN. Well, I would——

    Mr. LAYCOCK. Go ahead, Marc.

    Mr. STERN. You know, there are several things to be said. First I would not——

    Mr. SCOTT. It would not affect commerce?

    Mr. STERN. Yes. First, I would not yield by silence the notion that we haven't demonstrated extensive religious discrimination in the zoning area. I think we have. My own town in the last couple of months has turned down a Muslim mosque because there is not enough parking. It has turned down interracial, nondenominational church because there is not enough parking; and when a Methodist church wants to come in, somehow there is enough parking. And so, you know, I don't want that to go by silence.

    Mr. SCOTT. Well, that would be a situation where the law, if it just dealt with zoning——

    Mr. STERN. Right.
 Page 157       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Mr. SCOTT [continuing]. Would be narrowly tailored to address a specific problem.

    Mr. STERN. And, in fact, the statute specifically addresses zoning separately for precisely that reason, because we thought we made the record with regard to zoning, and we have special rules that apply to zoning. I think Professor Eisgruber was reading the act incorrectly. I think in his case it would not be the compelling interest test, which would be relevant, but the special rule for zoning that we have laid out, assuming the town made reasonable provision elsewhere for churches.

    But even as to commerce, several years ago there was a lawsuit in New York City about the way child care was delivered. It was mostly an Establishment Clause case. The city insisted, after a settlement, that Catholic youth homes, Catholic children's homes, were required to provide birth control teaching and materials, actual birth control devices, to children in its care. I have forgotten who the Cardinal was at the time, but he said he would close all of Catholic charities rather than violate church doctrine and teach contraceptive use to children in his care.

    And the same is true of Catholic and Baptist hospitals. If a State—and there are places where this is conceivable were to say that anybody who has got a license to operate a hospital has to perform abortions, I would expect that Catholic and many Baptist hospitals would simply close their doors. Now, that is going to have an impact on commerce.

 Page 158       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    In many parts of the country—I think, as Professor Laycock has said elsewhere about southern California, it is practically impossible to build a church anymore. Now, if you can't build churches in southern California, that is going to have an impact on the building industries and on these industries that deal with the provision of interiors of churches. So there are lots of things that will be affected.

    Will there be things that do not affect interstate commerce? Yes. We will not reach—we know that we do not reach every religious exercise under the Commerce Clause. It may well be, for example, that home schooling is not reached under the Commerce Clause. So there are things that are cut out, but there are lots of things that are in commerce and that are—we know from actual litigation experience, or actual regulatory conflicts, where if you don't have protection, commerce will dry up. The pool of commerce will be made smaller because government is allowed to regulate religion in ways that religion simply finds intolerable. In response religion will simply walk out of the marketplace.

    Ms. HAMILTON. If I could just add one point to that.

    Mr. CANADY. Well, I will tell you, I don't want to cut it off but we have gone already over 10 minutes, but you certainly will have an opportunity.

    Mr. Nadler.

    Mr. NADLER. Thank you.

    First of all, I ask unanimous consent to insert my opening statement, which I wasn't here to deliver in the record.
 Page 159       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Mr. CANADY. Without objection.

    [The prepared statement of Mr. Nadler follows:]

PREPARED STATEMENT OF HON. JERROLD NADLER, A REPRESENTATIVE IN CONGRESS FROM THE STATE OF NEW YORK

    Thank you, Mr. Chairman. I want to commend you for scheduling this hearing today and for introducing with me the Religious Liberty Protection Act.

    Although I have that uneasy feeling of deja vu, I believe that what we are doing today is necessary, though I find regrettable the fact that the Supreme Court has once again made legislation of this sort a necessity.

    In its Smith decision, the Supreme Court threw away decades of sound First Amendment law by holding that government could interfere with an individual's religious practice, even imprison that individual for practicing this religion, and the Constitution would permit it, so long as the government didn't single out that person's religion.

    So generally applicable laws, like zoning ordinances which exclude houses of worship, law which outlaw giving sacramental wine to children and other laws which have the effect of prohibiting the free exercise of religion, are ok. The government does not even have to show a compelling need for the law, nor does it have to show that there is another way to advance that public interest in a manner that is less restrictive on religion.

 Page 160       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    Congress responded with the Religious Freedom Restoration Act which the Court struck down in its Boerne decision, at least as applied to state laws, saying that Congress has exceeded its authority. I disagreed, but the Court does get the last word in these matters.

    What we are doing with the Religious Liberty Protection Act is to follow the Court's instructions in its recent cases and provide the protection we believe our First Freedom merits. At least that is what we are trying to do. The purpose of this hearing is to continue the process of making the factual record the Court has said it needs to demonstrate the Constitutional power and the factual basis for this legislation. I also look forward to hearing the testimony of the fine constitutional scholars who have argued this question from all sides, to clarify the source of our powers, and to ensure that our final product will pass muster with the Court. We will do no one any good if we simply pass another bill which is ultimately struck down.

    Religious liberty is threatened, not just because of bigotry, or hostility toward religion. It is in peril because sometimes the rules need to accommodate religion to protect it, and minority faiths, those lacking in political clout, cannot always depend upon the legislatures, whether it is a town council or the United States Congress, to grant them the leeway they need to observe their faith. We need federal civil rights legislation to ensure that, whether or not a religious minority has the clout to make the political branches of government respond, they can still be assured their right to religious liberty. It is my hope that this legislation will accomplish that goal.

    No American should be denied the right to religious liberty. With the passage of the Religious Liberty Protection Act, that right will once again be protected in a manner consistent with the Supreme Court's rulings.
 Page 161       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Thank you, Mr. Chairman. With that, I yield back the balance of my time.

    Mr. NADLER. Thank you. I think I am going to give Professor Hamilton the opportunity to comment. I was just going to ask her to comment on the—on Mr. Stern's interpretation of the Commerce Clause in this connection. Do you think it is too expansive?

    Ms. HAMILTON. It is twofold. It is much too expansive under the current Supreme Court's doctrine and the trend of its doctrine.

    The second problem is that he has transformed every aspect of the First Amendment into a subject of the Commerce Clause. The Commerce Clause is an enumerated power. The First Amendment is a limitation on Congress. You cannot say that all the subjects of the First Amendment are now enumerated powers. Congress was not originally intended to have any authority in this field. That it has any authority is only if it is acting appropriately with respect to an enumerated power on a particular topic in which it is solving a national problem. That is not the blueprint for this.

    Mr. NADLER. Or under the Enforcement Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.

    Ms. HAMILTON. Under the Enforcement Clause, which does not apply to Federal activities. It only applies to State activities, and there, only—as Boerne v. Flores says, only if you are enforcing what would be unconstitutional activity.
 Page 162       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Mr. SCHAERR. Could I respond to that, the question as to the scope of the commerce power?

    The most recent and somewhat controversial decision in that area, as the panel knows, is the—is the Lopez case, which said that Congress may regulate under the commerce power not in just one circumstance but in three different kinds of circumstances.

    First of all, the Court said Congress may regulate the use of the channels of interstate commerce. That is not what we have here. Second, they said Congress is empowered to regulate and protect the instrumentalities of interstate commerce. Again, that is not what we have here.

    But the third category is the key one. They said, finally, Congress' commerce authority includes the power to regulate those activities having a substantial relation to interstate commerce.

    So I think Mr. Stern's interpretation of the commerce power is exactly right. Even under the Lopez decision, which was viewed as somewhat of a restriction on the scope of Congress' commerce power, the Supreme Court has clearly indicated that this kind of legislation, just like traditional civil rights legislation, is still within Congress' power under the commerce—under the Commerce Clause.

    Mr. NADLER. Thank you.

 Page 163       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    Let me ask you this, Professor Hamilton: In your testimony on page 3, you state that RLPA's intervention in local land use law would set the pace for the most expansive invasion of State and local government authority in history. That is a quote.

    I have two questions. Doesn't this somewhat overstate the case? I mean, you have got statutes like the Clean Water Act, the Coastal Barriers Resources Act already intervening in what might be built where. And second, in Boerne, the Court made clear that where a factual record of free exercise violations exist, Courts may act using the—Congress, rather, may act using its section 5 Fourteenth Amendment power to craft a remedy.

    And in your letter to me of November of last year, you say, quote, if after due consideration Congress were able to identify an arena in which religious conduct is subject to or is highly likely to be subject to unconstitutional burdens, Congress would have the power to enact laws for the purpose of enforcing the Fourteenth Amendment's due process clause.

    So the question in the case of zoning is, where we have ample evidence of religion, of religion per se or particular religions, being singled out for discriminatory treatment under local zoning processes, is there any reason by reaching down to local zoning is an inappropriate use of our section 5 powers? And my follow-up question on that is if we have such evidence, do we have to have that evidence in individual cases, or is a nationwide pattern sufficient?

    Ms. HAMILTON. It is my view that you need persuasive evidence of a nationwide pattern of discrimination, but let's be careful about what we mean by discrimination.
 Page 164       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Discriminatory impact would not be sufficient. And as I understand most of the studies that I have seen on this issue, that is all that has been proven, that churches are disproportionately more likely to be affected. That does not prove discrimination. The free exercise clause, according to the Supreme Court, protects against especially discrimination which is targeting of a specific religion.

    Mr. NADLER. Especially or only?

    Ms. HAMILTON. Especially. The Smith decision is much more complex than it has been portrayed in hearings before this body. The Smith decision protects the free exercise of religion in a variety of contexts that have not been played out in the courts because RFRA was in the courts instead. Now that RFRA is no longer in the courts, we will see how the various exceptions to the generally applicable rule play out.

    So the answer is, you will need fairly persuasive evidence that there is a national practice of discrimination which amounts to targeting of particular religions. I have not seen any scholarly studies that support that claim. I have heard particular anecdotal claims that it happens in particular communities, but I have to tell you, I have received hundreds of phone calls, since I started the RFRA litigation several years ago, from various zoning activities. I have yet to have one which involved real discrimination. Most of them involve neighborhoods which are trying to find ways to work out the conflict between a church that is too large and the neighborhood is trying to exist as a neighborhood.

    Mr. CANADY. The gentleman's time has expired. The gentleman will have 5 additional minutes.
 Page 165       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Mr. NADLER. Thank you.

    Professor Laycock, we have been told that there is no precedent for the use of the least restrictive alternative standards. Didn't the Supreme Court employ that standard in the 1981 case of Thomas v. Review Board, and in what context?

    Mr. LAYCOCK. Thomas v. Review Board was an unemployment compensation case. Chief Justice Burger for, I think, seven Justices used the exact language of ''least restrictive means'' to summarize the Court's cases, and very similar language appears in the Sherbert case and the Yoder case, and those quotations are in a letter to Mr. Scott and the sponsors, and I will—with permission, I will have that letter entered into the record.

    Mr. NADLER. Thank you. I have another question for you, and then for perhaps Professor Hamilton to comment after you, sir.

    The bill has a blanket waiver of State sovereign immunity under the Eleventh Amendment. Can we do this after Seminole, and if so, how is what we are doing in RLPA distinguishable from Seminole and its progeny? And here I am thinking of a number of appellate court decisions which have invalidated section 106 of the Bankruptcy Code, and those decisions are causing all sorts of problems around the country.

    What is our constitutional basis, given the case law, for waiving the Eleventh Amendment here?
 Page 166       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Mr. LAYCOCK. The case law is Fitzpatrick v. Bitzer, and it is reaffirmed in Seminole Tribe. There is a lot of litigation going around the country, and the question in every case is was this statute, which attempts to override the immunity of States, enacted to enforce the Fourteenth Amendment, or was it only enacted under an Article I power?

    Everyone agrees that if it is enacted to enforce the Fourteenth Amendment, the override of immunity is valid. If it is a Commerce Clause statute, the override of immunity is not valid.

    It is often unclear which power Congress is using because it didn't matter before Seminole Tribe. Now it matters, but it is clear what the rule is.

    Mr. NADLER. Well, then I am confused. Given what the Supreme Court unfortunately said in Boerne, which is that our section 5 power is enforcement, not interpretation, how would—wouldn't the Court hold that given the fact that our sovereign immunity provision is not—is not based on the—premised on the Commerce or Spending Clause, but stands independently, wouldn't the Court almost inevitably hold that the sovereign immunity provision therefore falls squarely by itself on section 5 of the Fourteenth Amendment, which the Court in Boerne said can't be used for that purpose?

    Mr. LAYCOCK. No. The sovereign immunity override applies only to claims under section 3. Section 3, we believe, is a section to enforce the Fourteenth Amendment. We believe the hearing record is strong enough to support that. If the Court disagrees with us, if it strikes down section 3, the immunity override will go with it. But the immunity override is fine if section 3 is constitutional, and I believe it is. So the question is about section 3.
 Page 167       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Mr. NADLER. Okay. Could Professor Hamilton comment on the same thing? I would assume you agree with Professor Laycock.

    Ms. HAMILTON. Not exactly. The answer, I think, is complicated because I think the Court is in the process of working out its Eleventh Amendment jurisprudence and is moving toward increasingly more conservative positions.

    I think that if, in fact, that provision only applies to section 3, which I don't think is absolutely clear, but if that is true, then Professor Laycock's reasoning is probably correct.

    But let me add one more thing, and that is, I will just point you to page 2 of my testimony explaining why the least restrictive means test was not the test before 1990. The Supreme Court says so in the Boerne decision at page 7121. So I don't think we need to talk about cases before the Boerne decision when the Court has already said something different.

    Mr. STERN. The Supreme Court in Boerne also cited Gobitis without noting it had been overruled.

    Mr. NADLER. Also cited what?

    Mr. STERN. The Supreme Court, in Employment Division v. Smith also cited Gobitis without bothering to note that it had been explicitly overruled. I wouldn't take very seriously about what Justice Scalia said about what the law was or was not before he wrote his opinion in Employment Division v. Smith.
 Page 168       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    I would also, if I may, like to pick up on something that Professor Hamilton said is the standard for proving discrimination. She referred to scholarly studies of a nationwide pattern of an intentional effort to single out a single church. In the first place, there is nothing in any section 5 case that ever refers to scholarly opinions. And to the best of my knowledge, Congress has never used scholarly opinions as a basis for legislating before.

    The 1982 Voting Rights Act was almost entirely anecdotal and one-sided, I might add, but it was entirely anecdotal.

    Secondly, there is no requirement that a particular church be singled out. I just got finished telling a story about my town. I have been present when zoning officials have said, we don't want those people in because they are the people in the next town and we don't want them. And others have told those stories. You are going to hear more stories about that later today.

    I don't know what more you need. To say as Professor Hamilton does, that there has not been any showing of it is to stick your head in the sand. Every time somebody shows you evidence of it, you say that is not enough, or I don't believe that story, or it is not proven. And Congress can't legislate that way.

    Mr. EISGRUBER. Can I speak to that point, please?

    Mr. CANADY. We are going to have a second——

 Page 169       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    Mr. NADLER. A second round?

    Mr. CANADY [continuing]. Round, yes.

    Mr. NADLER. Okay.

    Mr. CANADY. So I will now recognize myself to conclude the first round.

    Let me start off by asking about a related issue. As has been mentioned, efforts are under way in various States to enact State RFRAs.

    Professor Hamilton and Professor Eisgruber, do you believe that the State RFRAs are constitutional?

    Mr. EISGRUBER. No, I don't believe that they are constitutional. One of the objections that we set forth in our testimony is related to Establishment Clause concerns and follows the concerns articulated expressly by Justice Stevens in the City of Boerne case.

    I think it is perfectly reasonable and desirable for both Congress and State legislatures to protect against incidents of insensitivity to religious interests, as this body has done before and as State legislatures have done before. But unfortunately, the model of the compelling State interest test, which has been the heart of the problem in both Smith and Boerne, has been copied in these statutes, and I think it creates serious constitutional problems and serious policy problems.
 Page 170       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Mr. CANADY. What is the serious constitutional problem with the State doing that?

    Mr. EISGRUBER. The serious constitutional problem is along the lines I mentioned earlier with the greenbelt example. But the example that Justice Stevens gave in City of Boerne may be equally good. As he said, if there is a historic preservation ordinance, it would equally prevent the remodeling of a church or the remodeling of a private school or the remodeling of any other charitable enterprise that might be taking place within that historic preservation district. By exempting churches and only churches from the strictures of zoning laws, one doesn't create a remedy for discrimination. What one creates is a special privilege. And that is unconstitutional under the Establishment Clause.

    Now, I should say here that I say with great confidence that I think the Commerce Clause and spending power arguments here would fail in the Court. The Establishment Clause issue is a bit harder. I agree with Professor Laycock that there are multiple precedents on this, Corporation of Presiding Bishops v. Amos, Thornton v. Caldor and Texas Monthly v. Bullock, and the trick is reconciling those three. I think the reconciliation of those three depends upon an argument about what makes sense and can't be somehow derived simply from what the Court has said thus far.

    Mr. CANADY. Professor Hamilton.

    Ms. HAMILTON. There are two questions in each of the States. One of them is whether or not there is a violation of the Federal Constitution. There is likely, in my view, an Establishment Clause problem, but I don't think that is a definite.
 Page 171       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    I think the second question is whether or not there is a violation of the State constitution. For example, many State constitutions have stronger Separation of Powers requirements than does the Federal Constitution.

    Mr. NADLER. Separation of Powers or Establishment provisions?

    Ms. HAMILTON. Separation of Powers under the State constitution, where there are many States that have provisions that require that the judiciary and the legislative branch do not overlap at all, unlike the Federal Government where more overlap is permitted. So the State constitutions themselves present particular problems.

    What is interesting about what is happening in the States right now is that each of the States has turned into a laboratory for a mini-RFRA. The State proposals are now being subjected to exemptions, because discussion has started with the interests that are being affected. In Florida there was a debate about whether or not the prisons ought to be exempted. In California, it looks to me like a fight to the death over whether or not the antidiscrimination laws will trump the mini-RFRA or the mini-RFRA will trump the antidiscrimination laws.

    So what is happening in states is the interests that weren't tapped in the RFRA hearings are now being tapped.

    Mr. CANADY. Okay. Let me give an example that has been posited by Professor Stephen Gey, that's G-E-Y. This is the example. It is the case of a female student whose religion does not permit her to bare her legs in public, but is compelled to attend gym class where, for aesthetic reasons, the students are required to wear shorts.
 Page 172       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Now, as I understand it, there are some particular religious groups that do, in fact, have problems with allowing members of the group to wear shorts in gym class or in any other context.

    Now, Professor Gey says that if an effort were made to accommodate that religious belief, to give the young lady a dispensation from having to wear shorts in gym class, that it would not be permissible. And he says, by ceding authority over the objecting student to the higher religious authority, the school board would subjugate democratic control of a particular policy area to a nondemocratic extrahuman force. That's the close of the quotation.

    And I will give myself 5 more minutes.

    Let me ask you this: Do you think there is a problem with the school authorities accommodating a student in this context on the basis of her religious beliefs? Professor Eisgruber first.

    Mr. EISGRUBER. No, I don't believe it is an Establishment Clause problem. I believe it is affirmatively desirable that she be accommodated. Indeed, I think that it is quite possible, if we fill out the facts of the case, that this may be a justiciable issue under the constitutional law as it stands after Smith, and I would be comfortable arguing under the First Amendment that this student ought to be accommodated.

    Let me mention to you a case from the Northern District of New Jersey, which I believe is currently on appeal to the Third Circuit, where the court vindicated a claim of this kind. There was a police officer in the Newark Police Department who was a practitioner of the Islamic faith and wanted to wear a beard. The Newark Police Department said, our officers have to be clean-shaven.
 Page 173       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    The officers went to court saying that their religious interests were being burdened, and the court very sensibly pointed out that other kinds of interests were accommodated within the Newark Police Department rules. So, for example, officers who developed a skin rash if they shaved were permitted to wear beards for that reason, and the court said, quite sensibly, that religious interests ought not to be treated worse.

    I think the police officers there are in the same position as the student you described. Accommodating that kind of interest isn't by any means subordinating the law of the State to a higher law by some external authority. What it is doing is accommodating interests in the same way we do for persons of all variety, and we ought to do that.

    Mr. CANADY. Professor Hamilton.

    Ms. HAMILTON. No, that is not a problem. And I think Justice Scalia made it absolutely clear in Smith that it is not a problem. In general, he said, generally applicable——

    Mr. CANADY. Let me ask you this: Do you think Justice Stevens would think that might be a problem?

    Ms. HAMILTON. Justice Stevens—how would you ever predict what Justice Stevens would do? I am not sure.

    Mr. STERN. Because he said so in Goldman.
 Page 174       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Ms. HAMILTON. Well, I think that——

    Mr. STERN. We don't have to predict it. He said so. The argument was presented in the context of military uniform regulation, and Justice Stevens said that the military regulation bearing the wearing of skullcaps had to be upheld because otherwise some people got to wear skullcaps, and others whose religious garb was more ostentatious or more visible, could not. And he said that the only way to keep the government neutral about religion was to let the government enforce its rules as they were written without any exception for religion.

    Now, that means—and that means, unless you have a rule of law that is entirely episodic, that this girl in this school has to wear the uniform that everybody else insists on, and there is lower case law to that effect, before the free exercise clause got taken seriously. It was an Alabama case.

    Ms. HAMILTON. Now wait a minute, wait a minute.

    Mr. CANADY. But you are assuming that his future actions could be predicted by his past actions.

    Ms. HAMILTON. Right.

    Mr. CANADY. In certain other contexts, when it comes to Justice Stevens, that is not accurate.
 Page 175       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Mr. STERN. I am sorry for taking Justice Stevens seriously.

    Ms. HAMILTON. I think that is some danger.

    Mr. EISGRUBER. I have to reserve time to respond, as a former law clerk to Justice Stevens.

    Ms. HAMILTON. The Smith decision is much more recent in which Justice Stevens joined in the opinion that said that accommodation from laws of general application should be left to the democratic process and to local control. This kind of accommodation, I don't think, poses any problem.

    There is a very good example in the State of California of how the process might work under the Smith world, if it ever is permitted to prevail. There was a widely publicized debate, about 3 to 4 years ago, on whether or not Sikh school children should be permitted to wear Kirpan (knives) in the public schools. The legislature widely debated it. It was discussed in the press. It was discussed among the people, and it was eventually voted down as being against the public interest. It is an example of the fact that these sorts of issues are capable of being intelligently discussed by people who are going to be affected by those particular kinds of rules.

    Mr. EISGRUBER. May I say one thing about the Stevens' ruling?

    Mr. CANADY. I am sorry. There is one other thing I want to ask, and we are going to have a second round so we will have an opportunity for you to say some more then.
 Page 176       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Let me ask you about Title VI under the 1964 Civil Rights Act. Why is what this bill proposes to do substantially different than what Title VI does, focusing just on the spending authority that is—provisions that are contained in the bill?

    Ms. HAMILTON. This bill institutes a standard that the Supreme Court has not used previously with respect to the Free Exercise Clause, in every arena where any Federal financial assistance is provided. That doesn't strike me as Title VI. Title VI is much more limited. This, once again, is the kind of broad brush approach that RFRA suffered from.

    Mr. EISGRUBER. I think my position is a bit different from Professor Hamilton's position about this. I do think the compelling State interest test is one that the Court has used and continues to use with respect to some aspects of the Free Exercise Clause, in particular the Lukumi Babalu Aye case that the Court decided involving actual discrimination against religion.

    I think the crucial distinction between Title VI and this exercise of the spending power is that Title VI is an antidiscrimination law, and because of the use of the compelling State interest test under these circumstances, this can't plausibly be regarded as an antidiscrimination law. That was the Court's message about congruence and proportion in Boerne, and that is what distinguishes RLPA from Title VI.

    Mr. CANADY. But what does antidiscrimination have to do with the commerce—with the spending power?

 Page 177       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    Mr. EISGRUBER. It has something to do with the spending power because one reason that no question ever arises about the constitutionality of Title VI is that Congress has plenty of power to do this under various headings, including, I think, section 5 of the Fourteenth Amendment. Here the claim is——

    Mr. CANADY. Well, all the Congress didn't think that.

    Mr. BERG. If I may, that is not entirely true. There are discriminatory impact rules in Title VI that wouldn't be justified by the Fourteenth Amendment on their own, and those would fall if Title VI were interpreted the way Professor Eisgruber suggests.

    Mr. EISGRUBER. As I said at the start of my remarks, I take a generous view of Congressional power and believe that the Court has done so in Boerne. And I think, as Justice Kennedy explicitly said, RFRA could not be understood as a discriminatory impact statute. I think the explanation for what is going on, if one is talking about laws that redress discriminatory impact, is that such laws may draw upon two sources; one, section 5 of the Fourteenth Amendment, and, second, the Commerce Clause cases where antidiscrimination has been understood as a reasonable way to open up markets.

    The difference in this statute is that Congress is saying, with regard to the Spending Clause components, that we have no other source of authority besides the spending power, and we are going to use that power to bootstrap an effort to regulate with regard to religious conduct.

    Mr. LAYCOCK. Even if that is a fair characterization of the statute, it is absolutely fine. All of this discussion has taken the focus in Boerne, that it has to be an antidiscrimination statute if it is enforcing the Fourteenth Amendment, and moved that focus, utterly without basis, to Article I where Congress can use its powers for whatever policy reasons make sense in its judgment. The Court has said over and over that Congress doesn't have to convince us that an Article I statute; policy is wise. It has to convince us that there is an affect on commerce. It has to convince us that the condition is reasonably attached to the Federal funds. It doesn't have to be an antidiscrimination law. I think it is an antidiscrimination law in some contexts, in some of its applications, but it doesn't have to be.
 Page 178       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Mr. CANADY. My time has expired.

    Mr. Scott.

    Mr. SCOTT. Thank you, Mr. Chairman.

    Mr. Schaerr, you mentioned the Lopez decision.

    Mr. SCHAERR. Yes.

    Mr. SCOTT. Guns were clearly within interstate commerce, but this regulation of guns had nothing to do with interstate commerce.

    Mr. SCHAERR. Well, it had no substantial affect on interstate commerce, that is, possession of guns on school property; that was what the Court concluded.

    Mr. SCOTT. Now, how do we get—use the Commerce Clause to get to local land use regulation under that—under that theory?

    Mr. SCHAERR. The bill doesn't try to rely on the Commerce Clause with regard to land use regulations. It relies entirely on section 5 of the Fourteenth Amendment.

    Mr. STERN. I think you can rely on the Commerce Clause to deal with zoning issues. I am not sure you have to—it is clear that the bill relies primarily on section 5 for the zoning statutes. However, given the difficulty that the discretionary power of zoning has created for churches in locating in new areas and following their members, given, the impact on the construction trades and the other trades and simply the ability of people to move where they want, because if their church isn't there, they are not moving there, I think there is a fairly direct connection with the commerce power, just as there was with regard to the public accommodation statutes of the 1964 Civil Rights Act.
 Page 179       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    If blacks from the North have a job but they can't go to the South because they can't get a hotel room and they can't do the business, they are not going to be hired in the North. And that had a deleterious effect on commerce, and that is the basis on which the Supreme Court based Title II of the Public Accommodations Acts of and the 1964 Civil Rights Act.

    Mr. SCOTT. And the Court in Boerne and other decisions went to great lengths to show that there was affirmative bigotry that motivated that behavior, and went to great lengths to say that the record was absent of such a record on religious bigotry.

    Mr. STERN. Well, it is true that the last time around, relying on some earlier statements of the Supreme Court, we did not make the detailed record perhaps that we should have.

    I have sat at zoning hearings where I represented a small storefront synagogue that wanted to move into a white town bordering on a largely black town. One of the commissioners said that if we allow this group in, we will be the next Paterson, which is the largely black town.

    I said to him that I thought that was an outrageous statement, and a zoning decision should not be based on bigotry of that sort. He then took offense that I was calling him an anti-Semite. I said, excuse me. I didn't call you an anti-Semite; I called you a racist.

 Page 180       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    That goes on. There is a case in the Second Circuit in which somebody incorporated a town because they didn't want Orthodox Jews moving into the area. We have a similar dispute in Ohio. The committee heard testimony about California.

    Mr. SCOTT. Is this bigotry aimed within different—at a specific religion?

    Mr. STERN. No, it is aimed at whatever religion is coming into a community that is not popular and not wanted. I have been called by Jewish——

    Mr. SCOTT. Wait a minute. But you are talking about minority religions, so you are treating one religion different from another religion?

    Mr. STERN. No, I am talking about whatever religion—there is no majority religion in this country. There are communities where there is a majority religion. I get calls from Jewish communities in Westchester saying, in all horror, the Church of Latter Day Saints wants to come into our community. What can we do to keep them out?

    The same communities have had litigation earlier when——

    Mr. SCOTT. Well, again, my point is that that is discrimination of one religion against another; not a national trend, but within a locality discriminating one from another.

    Mr. STERN. That is right. There is no national picked-on church.
 Page 181       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Mr. SCOTT. Can't an antidiscrimination law deal with that——

    Mr. STERN. Yes, because in each instance——

    Mr. SCOTT [continuing]. Rather than a law that creates a right for religion generally?

    Mr. STERN. Title VII of the 1964 Civil Rights Act bans national origin discrimination. There is no finding that any particular national origin was particularly worse off than others when Congress passed the law.

    If you look at the law, you will find all sorts of people have brought national origins claims, depending where you are in the country and who your employer is, and I think the same is true here. You will find different religious groups are treated differently in different communities, and Congress can find that problem is serious enough to treat in an omnibus fashion.

    Mr. LAYCOCK. I think Mr. Stern misunderstood the last question. In principle many of these cases can be dealt with in one-on-one antidiscrimination suits. The difficulty with that is that the standards in land use law are so vague, so discretionary, that it is almost impossible to prove in any one case that the ultimate reason for the decision was hostility to the group or its religion and not some vague land use consideration.

 Page 182       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    But this committee has before it both empirical studies and anecdotal evidence, and when you look at the whole pattern of cases, it is much easier to draw that inference. Then you have to draft a prophylactic statute to enable it to be dealt with one case at a time.

    Mr. CANADY. The gentleman's time has expired. The gentleman will have 5 additional minutes.

    Ms. HAMILTON. Representative Scott, it seems that when you ask about the Commerce and the Spending Clauses that you are accurately predicting the next federalism decision by the Supreme Court. A good example would be our chairman's example, the girl in the gym class in the public school in a small town in Alabama who doesn't want to reveal her legs. Now, that school is probably taking Federal funds of some sort. It is a public school. It would be covered by the plain language of the statute. Is there commerce power to regulate what the local school board does with respect to that particular student?

    Mr. CANADY. Would you yield?

    Mr. SCOTT. Go ahead.

    Mr. CANADY. The issue is not commerce, but spending authority.

    Ms. HAMILTON. The question is either one. Is there Commerce Clause power or, is there spending power there? Both are attempting to be——

 Page 183       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    Mr. SCOTT. But the fact that you have spending, the proscription has to relate to the spending, and in this case it would have nothing to do with spending.

    Ms. HAMILTON. There is no nexus on spending. Now you are with commerce.

    Mr. LAYCOCK. Of course there is a nexus to spending. If you drive her out of the school, she does not benefit from the Federal program to aid that school. That is the nexus here.

    Mr. SCHAERR. And they would also be using Federal spending effectively to engage in conduct that is harmful to religion.

    Mr. STERN. And that is exactly the basis the Equal Access Act—the Equal Access Act relies precisely on that power. Federal dollars flow to a school, not to the extracurricular club activities, but to the school, and the Supreme Court more or less unanimously upheld the constitutionality of that act.

    Mr. SCHAERR. If you want Federal funding, you have to respect religious freedom.

    Mr. BERG. I think there is a little bit of a tendency here to throw up as many objections as possible against the act, some of which are frivolous, in the hope that enough of those things will stick to strike it down. There are certainly some questions of the reach of the commerce power under the act. The act deals with those by saying that it is not going to apply where the Court would not view this as a regulation of commerce, but that doesn't speak to the other issues.
 Page 184       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Could I say one thing about the relationship again between the antidiscrimination point and this situation. I think what Professor Eisgruber and Professor Hamilton are saying would doom the Civil Rights Act of 1964 because what they are saying is that there is really a big difference between antidiscrimination and the protection of religious freedom from generally applicable laws.

    Well, if you look at the Civil Rights Act of 1964, it was about the difference between discrimination by the government and discrimination by private businesses. I can't think of a more fundamental division than between those two concepts. And the Court in the 1883 case that Congress had to deal with when they wrote the Civil Rights Act said that there is a great difference between private discrimination and public discrimination.

    You might have said in 1964 that this is a wholly different situation, and Congress, when attempting to legislate, would be struck down by the Court.

    Mr. SCOTT. The Court went to great lengths to differentiate the racial discrimination laws with referendum. Why wouldn't they do that again?

    Mr. BERG. They distinguished racial discrimination from effects of religious practice because under section 5 they were looking for discriminatory law.

    Under the Commerce Clause they—Congress is not limited to legislating against discriminatory laws.

 Page 185       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    Mr. SCOTT. Let me try to get to another issue because it applied to the discussion about the gym clothes.

    Is there a difference between the right to be accommodated and permissible accommodation; whether or not you have the right to give her an exception, or whether she has a right to be excepted?

    Mr. EISGRUBER. I would draw the following distinction between the way the ''right to accommodate'' and ''permissive accommodation'' are sometimes used. That is even after the decision in Smith, Free Exercise doctrine requires government, regardless of whether or not legislation of this sort is passed, to make accommodation in some cases. I think that is the case with regard to the young woman in the hypothetical with her school clothes. I also think that there are distances of permissive accommodation in which legislatures look for an area in which problems are arising and write legislation which creates a need for accommodation or a right to accommodation enforceable in the courts which would not otherwise exist.

    This has been—this is important, I think, actually to the case that was discussed before regarding Justice Stevens' views regarding yarmulkes in the military. Justice Stevens takes a very narrow view of what sorts of accommodations ought to be available as a right, and in the Goldman case he said he was very uncomfortable with the idea that judges would come in and decide, for example, which sorts of students should be exempted from which courses in schools or which sorts of military officers should be exempted from which uniform regulations.

 Page 186       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    But he has also clarified in United States v. Lee that his primary concern here is with equality, and I think he would uphold the law that Congress quite rightly passed in response to Goldman v. Weinberger which provides for an accommodation for individuals in those circumstances.

    Mr. STERN. If your concern is equality, the worst way to deal with accommodation is case-by-case. Case-by-case means that those religious groups that are powerful enough and alert enough to get an accommodation get one, and those groups which are not well-organized or very unpopular will not get one.

    You will not be able to get an accommodation of the Santeria in southern Florida, they are too unpopular. RLPA would allow them the same right to have their claims tested as the most powerful group in south Florida. The case-to-case approach is the least consistent with equality of any of the approaches.

    Mr. SCOTT. The issue of proportionality, what kinds of—if used in the Commerce Clause, which I think it has been described if we have gone too far, then it is not covered, so therefore you didn't go too far, what is covered and not covered in the context of proportionality to the response? The Supreme Court went to great lengths to say that RFRA was out of proportion to the problem. It covered too much. What is covered and not covered when you use the Commerce Clause?

    Mr. BERG. Again, I think we have to start by saying that proportionality in Boerne is a section 5 concept. It has to be proportionate to the Court's conception of the constitutional right being enforced. The Court believes that it has primary authority under constitutional rights. It had never believed that the courts have authority over regulating commerce.
 Page 187       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Congress doesn't have to be proportionate to the Court's conception of the problem when it is dealing with the Commerce Clause.

    Mr. EISGRUBER. It did insist in Lopez that there be a nexus requirement that had to be met in cases where the commerce power was invoked.

    Mr. BERG. There is a nexus requirement. It is not proportionality to a constitutional violation, it is substantial effect on commerce. That is the standard. And that standard obviously is to some extent case by case.

    If the Commerce Clause is interpreted as generously here as it has been in the Federal criminal laws, for example, you cause a $300 expenditure not to happen, and you have an impact on commerce because it might not otherwise have been spent.

    If they interpreted it less narrowly, we may affect only or primarily the rights of religious institutions. When the church is prevented from operating in the jurisdiction by exclusionary lands use regulation, for example, the impact on commerce is clear. In the church employment cases, the connection to commerce is clear. Nearly all employment relationships are regulated by law under the Commerce Clause. So there are some clear applications.

    There are number of debatable applications, and there probably will be litigation about those, and that is expected, but that is line-drawing litigation, it is about where the lines get drawn, not really about validity of the bill.

 Page 188       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    Mr. STERN. That is the plaintiff's burden in every case to demonstrate a nexus or substantial effect on interstate commerce.

    Ms. HAMILTON. Which is to say that this bill requires a case-by-case determination of Congress' power in every case involving religious conduct.

    Mr. SCOTT. Could I just make a comment? When we pass the law, we would like to have some idea what we are covering and what we are not covering, and this response is somewhat difficult.

    Mr. BERG. I think the difficulty comes from the fear that Professor Hamilton——

    Mr. SCOTT. If I may just finished. The chairman has extended my time twice. Thank you. I'm sorry.

    Mr. CANADY. The gentleman's time has expired. The gentleman from New York, Mr. Nadler is recognized.

    Mr. NADLER. I think I detected a slight area of distance between Professor Eisgruber and Professor Hamilton on the question of our young lady who doesn't wish to bare her legs in gym class.

    Professor Eisgruber said based on religious discrimination, you probably have constitutional authority to deal with that; and Professor Hamilton said that is the kind of subject that is necessary for legislative adjudication, presuming that we don't have authority to deal with that.
 Page 189       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Professor Hamilton, what disturbs me about the Smith decision and the City of Boerne decision, I want to quote Justice Jackson in the West Virginia Board of Education v. Barnett, one of the most famous quotes, and I am sure that you know it by heart before I read it.

    Mr. STERN. Robert, not Jesse.

    Mr. NADLER. I said ''Justice.''

    Mr. STERN. It is your New York accent.

    Mr. NADLER. ''The very purpose of a bill of rights was to withdraw certain subjects from the vicissitudes of political controversy, to place them beyond the reach of majorities and officials, and to establish them as legal principles to be applied by the courts. One's right to life, liberty and property, to free speech, free press, freedom of worship and assembly and other fundamental rights may not be submitted to a vote. They depend on the outcome of no elections.''

    That is the crux of everything that we are discussing here, and what you are saying is that young lady's rights depend on the outcome of local elections.

    Ms. HAMILTON. The way that the Court's doctrine has developed, there is not a requirement of mandatory accommodation from generally applicable laws unless you can prove discrimination or targeting. That is simply where the Court's jurisprudence is right now.
 Page 190       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    But I don't think that we should forget that religious belief and secular belief are absolutely protected. Government has no authority to dictate belief. What we are talking about here is only conduct.

    Mr. NADLER. But what you are saying is that when someone has a religious belief, that girl presumably is going to be expelled from the school, and she doesn't want to be expelled from the school and deprived of an education and perhaps subject her parents to prosecution for violation of the State's mandatory attendance laws. She has to violate her religion.

    Are you telling us we have no constitutional way of dealing with such a fundamental conflict to protect religious freedom in this country?

    Ms. HAMILTON. I am telling you that there are generally applicable neutral laws that do not have to give way to religion in any particular circumstance. That is what the Supreme Court has said the Constitution requires.

    Mr. NADLER. You are saying that the hundred-year-old decision in Reynolds that belief only is protected, we are back to that?

    Ms. HAMILTON. No. Reynolds said that conduct can be regulated at will.

    Smith said conduct can be regulated if you can prove the law is generally applicable, if you can prove it is neutral, if it is not subject to individualized discretionary decision-making, if it doesn't involve hybrid rights, et cetera. Smith is a very complex decision, and it does not deserve to be oversimplified and responded to on the basis of a misinterpretation.
 Page 191       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Mr. STERN. We are back to Reynolds if you have a better lawyer is what Professor Hamilton means.

    Mr. NADLER. Professor Laycock, as a follow-up, Justice Breyer said during the oral argument in Boerne, ''Let me take what you are saying and put in it this linguistic framework. Congress passed this prophylactically to prevent the violation, and now fill in the blank, what violation?''

    Solicitor General Dellinger responded, ''Where different religious denominations are treated differently, there is no question before, during or after Smith that that violates the Constitution. It may be difficult to remedy in a case-by-case judicial approach where you are trying to prove it, but it clearly is a constitutional violation if an exemption is made for the Methodist Church and an exemption is not made for Santeria.''

    This relates directly to the legislative process. For example, the House recently approved amendments to the Bankruptcy Code which allowed for religious and other charitable giving, both prepetition and during individual plan of reorganization, the so-called tithing bill. The bill provides a 15 percent safe harbor for prepetition tithes in which the debtor need not demonstrate a prior pattern of giving. Why 15 percent when the Scripture says 10 percent? Well, because the beliefs and practices of the Mormon Church were adequately protected when the chairman of the Judiciary Subcommittee in the Senate, who comes from Utah, insisted on that. And there is nothing wrong with having a chairman being aware of a particular religion and ensuring its protection in statute. That is not the problem.
 Page 192       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    The problem is that not all denominations are similarly situated, and not all of them have the chairman of the Judiciary Committee being well aware and solicitous of their interests. They can't get a hearing for their concerns. They may not have a lobbyist in Washington to alert them that they need to speak out.

    This sort of retail form of free exercise protection runs a real risk of omission, even with legislatures of the best of will. The real question is wasn't Dellinger right, and how do we assert that clear First Amendment violation under the Smith rules providing a basis for protection under our section 5 powers?

    Mr. BERG. I think Dellinger was clearly right when one denomination gets an exemption or gets protected and a different faith or denomination doesn't, that is a Smith violation.

    The problem is how do you prove it. One case at a time. Sometimes you can get the evidence, sometimes you can prove it. It is very difficult to do.

    Mr. CANADY. The gentleman's time has expired. The gentleman will have 5 additional minutes.

    Mr. NADLER. Thank you.

    Mr. BERG. We have seen plenty of examples of that kind of thing. It is local. It does depend on the political influence of different faith groups and different communities, although it is a bit of an exaggeration to say there is no national trend. There is in the record of an earlier hearing Gallup Poll data: 45 percent of the American people express hostility to minority religions and evangelicals, and 60 some percent or 80 some percent said that they wouldn't want to live next door to one.
 Page 193       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    There is—there is substantial evidence of very widespread hostility to people who take their religion more seriously than the norm. When rules are discretionary, when standards are vague as to in land use or certainly in the legislative process where you have discretion to pass a bill or not pass a bill, that kind of hostility matters.

    Mr. NADLER. I agree with you. On the radio in New York there was a report. It seems that some schoolteacher in the Bronx 2 days ago or a day ago led the class in a prayer to Jesus Christ and explained to all of the third-grade children that they ought to believe in Jesus Christ, and she was then fired for this. She was then fired as an improper exercise. And this is creating some controversy, and one individual citizen was quoted—not quoted, it was recorded, I heard him saying, ''This is terrible. She shouldn't be precluded from praying like that in school. It is terrible she was fired.''

    And the interviewer said, ''What if she prayed to Allah?''

    He said, ''Oh, then she should be fired,'' because that is not the right God.

    Professor Laycock, is it the case that you need a broad rule because of the difficulty of proof of discrimination, and that, in fact, you can justify that broad rule constitutionally on that?

    Mr. LAYCOCK. To the extent you are exercising section 5 power, you can justify the broad rule constitutionally to the extent that you have evidence of discrimination or lack of general applicability.
 Page 194       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    To the extent that you are exercising Article I power, spending and commerce, all of these concerns about how discrimination is hard to find and hard to prove are policy reasons why Congress should want to do this, but they are simply not necessary to the question of constitutional power. Congress can do it because it thinks it is sound policy, whether or not it thinks that there are lots of violations out there.

    One thing about your example from the Bronx, the person who made the mistake of going public and saying that praying to Jesus is different than praying to Alla—he can also whisper that to his friend on the school board, or a hundred people can whisper it to their friend on the school board, and we will never know about it, and it will never be in the hearing record, and you will never prove what the real motive was. You know that sort of thing goes on all of the time.

    Mr. NADLER. Thank you.

    Let me ask Professor Hamilton, I assume from the gist of your testimony that if we think that it is wrong for the State to use its power to put someone such as that schoolgirl and her parents in a position of violating their conscience or their religion or violating the law, of dropping out of school, being prosecuted for violation of the compulsory attendance rules, our only recourse is to pass a constitutional amendment, because the First Amendment does not prevent this and because Congress has no power to prevent that kind of abuse.

    Ms. HAMILTON. Smith says Congress can decide to accommodate, which is what they decided to do after the Smith decision. They decided to accommodate those who used peyote in Native American services. It is not that Congress has no options. It is that you've got a limit on what you can do, and the limit is the Establishment Clause. You can only go so far.
 Page 195       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Mr. NADLER. Everything that I have heard you say today in your arguments and in your written material is that Congress doesn't have the power to pass any kind of broad general rule that would place a limit on local legislative exercises that put people in that impossible situation unless the purpose of that legislative exercise was precisely to put people in that decision.

    If the purpose was something else, if the purpose was to say kids should have bare legs in gym class and not be inhibited in making the 4-minute mile by long pants, if that is the purpose, it happens to put people in a fundamental problem such as I described a minute ago, we have no power to protect people from that problem.

    Ms. HAMILTON. If you are asking me does Congress have the authority to engage in broad general lawmaking in the First Amendment arena, my answer is no.

    Mr. NADLER. My last question is: Assuming, God forbid, that your constitutional interpretation is again upheld by the Supreme Court, why shouldn't we pass a constitutional amendment to provide this kind of protection?

    Ms. HAMILTON. I will tell you why. I was at the annual convention of the American Atheists this weekend. It is the first time they have ever invited a believer.

    I heard many stories of people who are leading lives of quiet desperation because they live in neighborhoods where the church on the weekends is so busy they can't drive through their neighborhoods or where their children are ostracized in the schools.
 Page 196       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    I don't think that we have talked about the full universe of American citizens. We have talked about certain minority religions that allegedly are subject to majority control. We have not talked about all of the civil liberties that are of interest here, and I don't think that anyone in this room has sufficient information to justify RLPA's alteration of the relationship between church and state across the board.

    Mr. NADLER. May I have 2 more minutes?

    Mr. CANADY. The gentleman will have 2 more minutes.

    Mr. NADLER. Are you saying that if you pass legislation that would stand up—let's assume that it would stand up to scrutiny. If you pass legislation that would protect people from an unintended conflict between their fundamental conscientious rights—and the Supreme Court, bear in mind, in the conscientious objector cases said that it doesn't have to be an established religion or any religion, it can be a fundamental conscientious belief that is equivalent to that person of a religion, it doesn't have to be a religion. But if we were to say that we are going to protect people from being put in that impossible position, that that somehow burdens atheists or other people? And if so, how does it burden them? How does it burden an atheist or anyone else to say, I cannot be forced to choose between—if I were a woman—baring my legs in class or violating my religion or wearing a yarmulke in the Army or in prison and violating my religion; how does it burden anybody to enable me to live with my conscience within the law?

    Ms. HAMILTON. Because you are choosing a judicial standard that draws the boundary of power between a democratically-enacted law and a religious believer. The question in a zoning case is whether or not the people who have spoken through their representatives and enacted zoning laws are going to trump, or whether the religious believer is going to trump. This is truly a zero-sum game.
 Page 197       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    If you adjust the balance of power so that the religion has more power to defy the historical preservation law, you are going to make unhappy those who wanted a historical preservation law in the first instance.

    There is not a single generally applicable law that you can name with that does not have that same characteristic. And let me give you the City of Boerne, Texas. In Boerne, Texas, the people saw each other every day walking up and down the street, and they were in great discord over whether or not the church should have the addition or not. There was going to be a winner or loser, and it depended on where the line of power was drawn between the two parties. There is always a loser if someone is, in fact, a winner. This is about power.

    Mr. LAYCOCK. There is sometimes a loser. In the gym shorts case there is no loser if you accommodate that person, and even when there is a loser, it is often that zero sum. If there is some statute in place that enables the religious side to force the city to sit down and talk with it, in many of these cases we find out that there is a solution which minimizes the cost to each side. But you can't start that conversation if you have no legal rights.

    Mr. CANADY. The gentleman's time has expired.

    Mr. NADLER. May I have enough time for Professor Eisgruber to respond?

    Mr. CANADY. Yes. The gentleman may have 1 additional minute.
 Page 198       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Mr. EISGRUBER. As Representative Nadler suggested, I find myself in considerable disagreement with Professor Hamilton. I do think there is power within State legislatures and Congress to make reasonable accommodations for religious belief.

    In response to your question, Representative Nadler, about where the hypothetical student that Representative Kennedy described could turn in the absence of RLPA, I think there are two kinds of answers, perhaps three, to keep in mind.

    One, I think there is a strong claim under the Free Exercise Clause of the Constitution because we are dealing not with a neutral and generally applicable law, but rather with a discretionary regulation made by schools.

    Mr. NADLER. If that were passed by the city council, that would be different, in your opinion?

    Mr. EISGRUBER. I think it would work differently if there was a specific law passed by the city council.

    Secondly, I think we should remember that this is not simply a matter of Congress to the rescue or no help. That is, our State and local governments are often involved in all sorts of claims that are raised that are ugly, and sometimes they behave poorly, but sometimes they behave very well, and we should keep in mind in particular our State supreme courts which often do a very good job.

 Page 199       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    I don't know what Mr. Stern says when his friends in Scarsdale call him about excluding churches from their neighborhoods. When I was consulted by a community in New York which wanted to exclude a religious group, what I told them, as I read the Constitution, churches and schools are exempt from the kinds of regulations that you want to apply. I don't think there is any constitutional argument against that, and I think you have to let them in.

    The third thing I would say is it is not a choice even in Congress between RLPA and nothing. What Congress did to accommodate the special needs of the disabled, for example, was to enact a reasonable accommodation standard in the Americans with Disabilities Act. I think that has been a useful assistance to the rights of the disabled. I am not quite sure why this issue and this issue alone gets a different test, one that we haven't applied to the disparate impact of discrimination in the area of racial discrimination.

    Mr. STERN. I think if you look at the handicap legislation, and certainly this is true of religious accommodation, where reasonable accommodation is the standard, that standard proves to be no standard at all.

    That is the standard currently for prisoner complaints across the board with constitutional claims, and it is absolutely a useless standard because it has no teeth at all. It is easily evaded. Even the rule about the girl and the gym clothes is reasonable in terms of accidents or minimizing insurance cost, and you can be sure that school officials will assert those things and meet a standard of reasonableness.

    I don't understand, I must say, how Professor Eisgruber thinks that the New York State constitutional rule exempting or greatly minimizing the zoning authority of local authorities over churches is consistent with the argument in his memorandum about the nonestablishment of religion. I think that those are two entirely inconsistent doctrines.
 Page 200       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Mr. CANADY. The gentleman's additional additional time has expired, and I will now recognize myself.

    Mr. NADLER. Thank you, Mr. Chairman.

    Mr. CANADY. I want to go back to the point that Professor Hamilton was making about the whole business of drawing lines and having winners and losers and part of the free flow of debate in communities.

    An example that I thought of earlier when Mr. Nadler was listing some of the examples, he listed congressional action, and one which did not happen to be on his list was the Fair Housing Act. Under the Fair Housing Act, the Congress has acted to help ensure that people with handicaps are not—have an opportunity to have housing opportunities and that people are not discriminated on the basis of their familial status. Some of us may have differences of opinion about the proper scope of that Federal action, how much latitude should be given to the local governments, but all of us agree that there is a proper role for the Federal Government there.

    Just listening to this whole discussion today, it is hard for me to understand why the Federal Government can use its power under the Commerce Clause in that context to vindicate the values that are vindicated by congressional action, and the Congress would be excluded from using its power under the Commerce Clause and the spending power to protect the values related to religious liberty.

 Page 201       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    I understand the road we have been down with respect to section 5. I thought that was a good choice that in the eyes of the Supreme Court we were mistaken, but to say that that would now exclude us from making a comprehensive serious attempt to address the problems that exist when people face having their consciences coerced, when they face the coercive power of government, and they face either having to sacrifice their religious beliefs or comply with government, and they are put in the position of making that choice, for us to say that we are now going to be able to enter that arena in the same way that we have entered the arena pursuant to the spending power and the civil rights context just does not make sense to me.

    If we can do what we have done under Title VI, and Title VII for that matter, of the 1964 Civil Rights Act, I believe that we can act to protect religious freedom in a way that is closely modeled on that statutory basis.

    And I would just like to open it up to Professor Laycock and Berg and Mr. Schaerr to make any comments in response to the claims that have been made about the inadequacy of congressional power under the Commerce Clause and the spending authority to accomplish what we are attempting to accomplish in this legislation.

    Mr. SCHAERR. I agree with your comments that there has been so much discussion about so many different kinds of potential constitutional objections to this legislation that one could get the false impression, and I think it is a false impression, that there is a big dark constitutional cloud hanging over this bill, but I really do not think that is true. When you take each of the arguments and you look at them closely and compare them with the Supreme Court's case law on those issues, and when you compare them with what Congress has done in other contexts, especially in the discrimination context, the arguments, in my view, just evaporate.
 Page 202       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    I think this legislation is constitutional and would have a very good chance of being upheld. And it also seems to me that it would be a tragedy to have a situation in which, for example, the commerce power and the spending power are used to pursue other values, many of which are very important, but not also to use those powers to protect religious freedom, which I think all of us would agree is certainly among the most important values that there are in our society.

    Mr. BERG. I would second all of those things and ask or sort of comment again that the raising of lots and lots of different objections can give the impression that there is just no way that the bill can be constitutional, but a good portion of the objections that we have heard today I just think have very little basis. And while there are a couple of constitutional issues with respect to this bill as to how far it can go under the commerce power particularly, I view those as entirely different from the sort of question about whether Congress has power to act in this area at all.

    Just to say a word about the religious liberty issues, I think we——

    Mr. CANADY. My time has expired. I will give myself 5 additional minutes.

    Mr. BERG. It seems to me that it stands religious liberty on its head to say, as we think about these two clauses in the Constitution of Free Exercise and nonestablishment, that the establishment provision is going to prevent Congress from taking any kind of action with respect to ensuring religious liberty.
 Page 203       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    The Free Exercise side of the First Amendment speaks more directly, it seems to me, to the issue of leaving religious believers alone, far more directly than the Establishment Clause speaks to that issue. The Establishment Clause speaks to tax support for religion. It speaks to government-sponsored religion. It is out of its place dramatically, it seems to me, when it is used to address the issue of whether religious exercise can be left free from legal restriction.

    Mr. CANADY. Professor Laycock?

    Mr. LAYCOCK. I agree with all of that, and I would emphasize a couple of other things.

    Much of these objections, particularly Professor Hamilton's, are based on a bet that the Supreme Court is changing the rules. She said that they are interpreting congressional powers more narrowly. What is going to be the next Lopez and so forth.

    Maybe the Supreme Court will change the rules, although I think they would have to change them very dramatically to erode the spending power and the commerce power so far that this bill would run into significant constitutional difficulty.

    But I don't think Congress should be paralyzed by fears of what the Court might do in the future without any basis in its precedents from the past. I think if you look at what the Court has decided for the past 60 years, this bill is clearly within congressional power. And I think the hypothetical from Professor Gey that the chairman mentioned, about the girl in gym shorts, is very revealing as to where much of the objection to this kind of legislation ultimately starts from. It is mostly an academic objection, and from the American Atheist Society, and then it gets picked up by interest groups who come into conflict with religious groups.
 Page 204       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    You quoted Gey as saying that the problem with letting the girl wear long sweats instead of gym shorts is that it would subjugate democratic policy to her God. That is what this is about.

    The objection to exempting burdened religious practices is about the ultimate supremacy of majoritarian control and imposing majoritarian secular values on every member of a religious minority group who has an objection. Sometimes, unfortunately, the conflict is unavoidable, and we have to impose those values because of the impact that the person is having on other people. But the gym shorts example puts it clear. There is no impact on anybody except forcing that girl to drop out of school or violate her conscience, and the academic claim is that her religion has to be subjugated to the democratic process. I think that is exactly what the First Amendment was intended to prevent. The Supreme Court now disagrees; it said you have a right to believe a religion, but no right to practice it. To the extent that Congress has power under Article I, it ought to restore the right to practice religion to the American people.

    Mr. CANADY. Thank you, Professor.

    I want to thank all of the members of this panel for your very helpful testimony. I think we have had a good cross-section of opinion on these very important issues. Each of you have made a significant contribution to the considerations of the subcommittee, and we thank you for taking the time to be with us today.

    We will now go to our second panel.

 Page 205       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    Mr. CANADY. I want to thank the members of the second panel for joining us today. Our first witness on the second and concluding panel of today will be Mr. John Mauck. Mr. Mauck is an attorney with the law firm of Mauck, Bellande & Cheely in Chicago, Illinois. And I apologize to your partners if I have mispronounced their names.

    Finally, we will hear from Professor Cole Durham of Brigham Young University Law School. We appreciate your participation in the hearing today.

    We would ask that you do your best to summarize your testimony in 5 minutes or less. Without objection your full written statement will be made part of the permanent hearing record. Observing the proceedings thus far this morning, you will note that we are not strictly enforcing the 5-minute rule.

    Again, we thank you.

    Mr. Mauck.

STATEMENT OF JOHN MAUCK, ATTORNEY, MAUCK, BELLANDE & CHEELY, CHICAGO, IL

    Mr. MAUCK. Thank you, Mr. Chairman. My practice has been involved in land use, so I would like to confine my testimony to the land use aspects of the bill before you.

    Churches come in all sizes and shapes. You may be aware that there are megachurches now along with house churches, groups of 5 and 10 and 15 people that meet in homes and storefronts. Churches come in many sizes and shapes. They come also in many religious denominations, but there is an overlapping ethnic and racial aspect, churches that group along ethnic lines, such as Korean, Hispanic, Afro-Americans, Albanian Orthodox, and as we have been talking about the power to regulate, I think we should realize that this is substantially and often a racial and ethnic issue as well as a religious issue.
 Page 206       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    I am involved particularly in zoning applications for churches and would like to tell the committee about a number of times that churches have been discriminated against in attempts to obtain zoning permits.

    I represented one Hispanic church that attempted to get a permit in a suburb of Chicago. The mayor told the city manager, ''We don't want Spics in this town.'' The only reason that I know that is that the city manager went to his priest and asked what to do, and the priest said, ''you are going to have to risk your job. What you are being asked to do is evil.'' The city manager came and told me and he lost his job about a week later.

    In the Marquette Park area of Chicago, which is a traditionally white area where Martin Luther King marched and was pelted a number of years ago, there is a dividing line called Western Avenue. It is a commercial street. To the east of Western Avenue is almost entirely Afro-American, and to the west is almost entirely Caucasian. Faith Cathedral, an Afro-American church, purchased a funeral parlor about 100 feet west of Western Avenue. It was not on the commercial area, but it abutted the commercial area and residential area. They planned to use this funeral parlor as a place of worship. It had adequate parking. It had a chapel. It was set up for the type of assembly use that churches need.

    It was also the biggest crowd that I have ever seen at a zoning hearing in the city of Chicago. There were probably some 30 white people there from the community objecting. And the zoning board turned down the application. The zoning board did not have to give a specific reason. They can say it is not in the general welfare, or they can say that you are taking property off the tax rolls. Most zoning statutes have large discretion to the city in determining whether to issue a permit. The zoning board would never say, we are turning you down because you are Afro-American, but I don't think that they had to in that case at least to convince me that racism motivated the turn down in some way.
 Page 207       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    In downtown Chicago there has not been a new church built in 20 to 25 years. There are large existing churches, but I have an Afro-American church client that tried to locate between the United Center, where the Bulls play, and the Loop, and where there is about an 8- to 10-block stretch that is developing. The reason they wanted to locate there was to provide a church for Afro-Americans, particularly young professionals. New churches have been shut out of the loop, as I said, except for the traditional churches that have been there for a long time. And the city did not want any churches in that area to gum up their planned commercial development.

    The church then went to another area nearby, across from the Presbyterian Administration Building, and they were told by the city, ''we might want to make this into a night club district, and your presence would interfere with our development.''

    Finally, the church moved down to the south side and found a funeral home. And the city said, fine, you can move there. It was an all Afro-American neighborhood, and I think the city was glad to be rid of a pesky challenge.

    A small group of 20 Hispanic believers attempted to buy a building in the city of Chicago that was a formerly a florist shop, and the alderman didn't want them in the neighborhood, and so he changed that floral shop into a manufacturing zone. A 25-foot by 125-foot piece of land became a manufacturing zone.

    A Vineyard Church attempted to buy a theater, one of these 1920 art deco theaters, and they were going to make that into their assembly hall and worship facility. The alderman changed that into an manufacturing zone.
 Page 208       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    A Currency Exchange on the south side of Chicago, a church attempted to buy that, and while their application for permit was pending, the alderman decided let's make that into a manufacturing zone.

    These laws can be abused. Some of the cases were litigated, but I think you need to understand that in the area of land use, judicial remedies often are not available. The churches don't have the money, or the municipalities can wait them out because a church has a choice of buying a building that it can't use or having to carry the expense and pay the mortgage every month, if it can get a mortgage, on a building that it can't use, or walking away. To continue and then sue the city and force them to allow you to use the building can take 3 or 4 years, and often it is not possible. So the cases reported in the legal system are just the tip of the iceberg. Discrimination is all over the place, and there is good reason to remedy that.

    The Religious Liberty Protection Act proposes three solutions which I think are reasonable. One is that there be equal protection; wherever you allow a secular assembly, why not allow a religious assembly? Why discriminate on the basis of the content of the discussion that is going on? If there is allowed a meeting hall discussing great books, why not allow a religious assembly discussing the Bible?

    The second problem is that many cities have ordinances that do not allow churches freely anywhere within the city. They must get a permit to get into the city. And this is not true, of course, of residential uses or commercial uses or many other types of uses. They all have choice where to locate. But in approximately half of all city ordinances that I have read, and this would be across the country because my practice ranges across the country, approximately half of the ordinances I see do not have any zone where a church can freely go. They must get a special use permit which requires a public hearing and public approval to permit those churches to go in, and there is a real Establishment of Religion problem here because municipalities decide what churches they want, what folks they want in their community.
 Page 209       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    And municipalities also need the help of a Federal law too so that they will be not be inundated with religious uses. Certain communities have had very easy access to churches and found that a lot of churches come to them because other communities put up high barriers. Those communities with low barriers are suddenly fearful that they are going to get too many churches, and so they put their barriers up higher. So these communities have to compete against each other and worry that if they don't have a higher barrier, they are going to be inundated with tax-exempt uses.

    But the Federal Government is in a unique position to say, because of these fears in the community, we are going to have an across-the-board law that is the same for everyone, and then communities won't have to have fears about raising higher barriers to keep churches out.

    Mr. CANADY. Thank you, Mr. Mauck.

    [The information referred to follows:]

59929a.eps

59929b.eps

59929c.eps

59929d.eps
 Page 210       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

59929e.eps

59929f.eps

59929g.eps

59929h.eps

59929i.eps

59929j.eps

59929k.eps

59929l.eps

59929m.eps

59929n.eps

59929o.eps

59929p.eps

 Page 211       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
59929q.eps

59929r.eps

59929s.eps

59929t.eps

59929u.eps

59929v.eps

59929w.eps

59929x.eps

59929y.eps

59929z.eps

59929aa.eps

59929ab.eps

59929ac.eps
 Page 212       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

59929ad.eps

59929ae.eps

59929af.eps

59929ag.eps

59929ah.eps

59929ai.eps

59929aj.eps

59929ak.eps

    Mr. CANADY. Professor Durham

STATEMENT OF W. COLE DURHAM, JR., BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW SCHOOL

    Mr. DURHAM. Thank you. It is a great honor for me to address this body today on legislation vital to protecting one of our preeminent liberties: religious freedom. I have spent much of the past decade working in support of this great principle both in my home State of Utah and at the Federal level, work which underscores my sense that we are dealing with one of the bedrock principles of any just society.
 Page 213       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    It is a true tragedy that some of the most fundamental problems arise in this area, and some people seem to think that they can't be dealt with at the Federal level. I believe that the proposed law is measured, that it does follow what has been done in other areas. For example, it involves valid assertions of the commerce and spending powers.

    I also want to focus primarily on the land use issues. I think I must have misheard Marci Hamilton. I thought she said land use is the last bastion of liberty. I cannot believe that. I have to say that I must have misheard her.

    Mr. CANADY. My ears heard the same thing with the same response on my part.

    Mr. DURHAM. Maybe she misspoke, but certainly anyone who has been in any of these processes I know often have questions and problems with that.

    One of my fundamental roles in this hearing is to draw together anecdotes—cases—on land use planning. There is a reason that we deal with anecdotes in this area, and that is that every piece of land is different; land is unique. And yet there are recurring kinds of problems.

    A year or so ago when we were preparing the amicus briefs in the Boerne case, I along with some other colleagues pulled together all of the reported cases that we could find regarding land use and religious freedom. We tabulated them and simply looked at what happened. The result is not a scientific study in the strict sense. Frankly, I don't know how one would assemble a scientific universe of such cases. Instead, we simply tried to get all of the reported cases. When you look at them, you see an overwhelming pattern of discrimination.
 Page 214       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    This, of course, goes to the section 5 issue and section 5 support for the land use provisions of Religious Protection Act.

    Let me just summarize very briefly what the overall results are. I am skipping over another study that was done by DePaul University that looks at the scope and the range of land uses that are done by churches throughout the country. This was a survey of about 300 major denominations and what their land use patterns are.

    But focusing just on this collection of data about the actual cases, we compared the treatment received by smaller religious groups. This is a continuum, but we took those with 1.5 percent of the population or less and we compared those with the treatment that is received by larger religious groups. Minority religions that fall in the category of having less than 1.5 percent of the population represent about 9 percent of the total population of the United States.

    Mr. SCOTT. What percent?

    Mr. DURHAM. About 9 percent. These small groups represent only 9 percent of the population, and yet they were involved in over 49 percent of the cases regarding the right to locate buildings at a particular site and over 33 percent of the cases seeking approval of accessory uses.

    When we did the study, you couldn't exactly tell which kind of denomination was involved in each case. If the case name is ''Roman Catholic diocese such and such,'' you know that it is Catholic, but some of the others are not so obvious. So there were a number of cases that are unclassified or are from unascertainable denominations. These unclassified cases are likely also to be in the category of small religious groups (with less than 1.5 percent of the population).
 Page 215       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    It turns out that the disproportionate burden becomes even more distressing when these cases are taken into account. If these are counted in, over 68 percent of the reported location cases, and over 50 percent of the accessory use cases involve smaller religious groups.

    There may be some imperfections in the data, but there could be substantial error without disturbing the result. The point is this portrays a picture of significant recurring discrimination.

    I think, as Mr. Mauck said, we are just seeing the tip of the iceberg. I can walk through a number of cases, as my testimony does, and you see churches being driven from pillar to post seeking place after place simply in order to find a place to worship, and this is, in my view, unconscionable.

    Now, it is true that there are all sorts of planning reasons that one can give for such results. I want to say that most of the planning people in this country act in good faith and so forth, but I think that they end up suffering from what I call ''secular blindness.'' They are often more concerned about some relatively minor concern about aesthetics and the like than they are with responding religious freedom. As important and valuable as these concerns are, they cannot outweigh the value of religion and religious freedom in our society. It is vital to adopt a law like the Religious Liberty Protection Act to deal with these things.

    In conclusion, I would simply underscore what was said at another point in my written testimony with respect to the Commerce Clause issue. Commerce issues are particularly obvious in the land use area. Religious use of land has all kinds of impacts on commerce, and the impacts are clearly substantial. Religious uses are directly burdened by the land use decisions, and it is perfectly permissible for Congress to exercise its power to deregulate this area that is so vital to exercise one of the most fundamental freedoms in the world.
 Page 216       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Thank you.

    Mr. CANADY. Thank you, Professor.

    [The prepared statement of Mr. Durham follows:]

PREPARED STATEMENT OF W. COLE DURHAM, JR., BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW SCHOOL

    This statement is submitted by Professor Durham in his personal capacity, and is not made on behalf of any organizations or institutions with which he is affiliated.

    It is a great honor for me to address this body today on legislation vital to protecting one of our preeminent liberties: religious freedom. I have spent much of the past decade working in support of this great principle: in my home state of Utah, at the federal level, and as a comparative law expert in many of the countries emerging from the yoke of communism. Experience in all these contexts has reaffirmed my conviction, in setting after setting, that religious freedom is one of the bedrock principles of any just human society. As Madison rightly argued over two centuries ago in his famous Memorial and Remonstrance, religious freedom ''is in its nature an unalienable right'' because it relates to duties that are ''precedent, both in order of time and in degree of obligation, to the claims of Civil Society.''(see footnote 100)

    While this hearing rightly focuses on issues of United States constitutional law, it is worth remembering that the principle of religious freedom is deeper and more absolute than any constitution. The Universal Declaration of Human Rights, whose fiftieth anniversary is celebrated this year, clearly recognized (as did our founding fathers) that religious freedom is not a right conferred on individuals by states; it is a right possessed by everyone simply by virtue of being human. Our Constitution is hallowed in no small part because it was one of the first great charters of human history to protect the deeper principle of religious freedom. Moreover, our constitutional history as a people remains impressive because of ongoing efforts to protect this cherished liberty. The legislation we are discussing today, if enacted, will be part of our generation's elaboration of the American heritage of religious freedom.
 Page 217       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

I. GENERAL CONSIDERATIONS CALLING FOR ADOPTION OF THE RELIGIOUS LIBERTY PROTECTION ACT

    Congressional action is vital because religious freedom faces unique challenges at this juncture in our history. These challenges are not limited to the fact that the United States Supreme Court has radically and unnecessarily narrowed the scope of religious freedom protections as traditionally understood in this country.(see footnote 101) They flow from the pervasiveness of the modern state, the increasing pluralization of culture, and powerful forces of secularization. Each of these three factors intensifies the need for added protection of religious freedom.

    This is most obvious as one considers the massiveness of the modern state. The seemingly inexorable expansion of state activity into more and more sectors of life increases the number of areas in which state and religious activity can come into conflict, and where religious freedom protections are vital to protect individual and collective religious activity. This Hearing, previous hearings on the legislation in question, and all the hearings on the earlier Religious Liberty Protection Act, were replete with evidence of the many areas in which religious freedom is threatened if encroaching governmental action is not strictly scrutinized.

    The increasing pluralism of contemporary society further compounds the potential friction points between religious activity and the state. Some, including Justice Scalia in the Smith decision, have cited this factor as an argument against accommodation of religious difference. But this runs counter to our historical experience. What the American experiment has shown, and shown stunningly (if not always perfectly), is that accommodation and toleration are much more effective in promoting social stability and flourishing than insistence on homogeneity and standardization. Increasing pluralism calls for more, not less religious freedom, because in addition to being right, respect for difference pays richer social dividends than wooden insistence on conformity.
 Page 218       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Less obvious, perhaps, is the challenge posed by progressive secularization, which is particularly evident among our intellectual elites. Secularization is gradually dulling our sensitivities to the vital importance of religion and religious freedom to the strength of our republic. The importance of religion to society was obvious to the founders and to many of the greatest commentators on American life, such as Alexis de Tocqueville. But in secularized minds, the legitimate interests and claims of religion seem to fade in importance or to be marginalized when balanced against the secular interests that are the focus of most governmental programs. Secular purposes look neutral, even when they have severe ramifications for religious life, whereas religious beliefs are suspect. What results is a kind of secular blindness, or at least myopia, that results in progressive underprotection of religious rights.

    This trend is compounded by those thinkers about religious rights, including some at this hearing today, who advocate various versions of what might be called ''secular reductionism.'' Some contend that religious rights can simply be reduced to other more secular rights, such as freedom of speech, or association, or the right to equal protection. Others view religious freedom through a paradigm of equality, in which the idea of religious freedom is reduced to a mere non-discrimination norm. Too often, even the residual equality norm to which religious freedom is reduced grows insensitive to the value of religious difference. It is axiomatic in dealing with equality norms that substantive equality cannot be achieved without taking relevant differences into account. But secularized equalitarians are all too prone to forget that religion and the right to religious freedom constitute relevant differences that need to be taken into account in order to provide genuine substantive equality. Whatever one ultimately thinks about the balance of liberty and equality, it is fair to say that the greatness of our tradition in religious liberty will be impoverished if we do not understand that at its core it is about the protection of religious differences, religious pluralism, and religious conscience, and that sometimes these values are so strong that they even override otherwise relevant equality claims.
 Page 219       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    The Religious Liberty Protection Act helps remedy the foregoing problems by insisting, at least in those areas where Congress has continuing power after Boerne, that governmental incursions on religiously motivated conduct shall be strictly scrutinized. This does not mean that all state action and state norms thus scrutinized will be invalidated. No one has ever claimed that the right to engage in religiously motivated conduct is absolute. But it does assure that government officials cannot ride roughshod over religious claims, that they will need to bear the burden of proving that state action they implement complies with constitutional requirements, and that they need to consider carefully whether they can structure their programs in ways that are less burdensome to religious believers and organizations. Only when they have strong justification will they be allowed to override religious concerns. Insisting on such justification does not constitute an unfair privileging of religion. To the contrary, it simply recognizes the distinctive protections afforded by the First Amendment. Religious differences need to be taken into account to avoid unfair disadvantaging of individuals and groups bound by conscientious obligations. Requiring special sensitivity affirms the distinct and sensitive role that religion plays in social life; state action that fails to respect its distinctive character is unjust.

II. THE NEED FOR SPECIAL PROTECTION OF RELIGIOUS FREEDOM IN THE FIELD OF LAND USE PLANNING

    When I was invited to appear at this Hearing, I was asked to focus in particular on religious freedom issues that arise in the area of land use. In the balance of my remarks, I will turn to this area. In my view, the problems encountered by religious organizations in the area of land use are symptomatic of a larger set of problems that religious organizations face in the modern regulatory state. Thus, I hope my remarks in what follows will be understood both as documentation of concerns in the land use area in particular and at the same time as a case study providing evidence more generally of the need for the Religious Liberty Protection Act.
 Page 220       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Conflicts between free exercise of religion and land use date back to the earliest days of the American colonial period. One of the most famous early cases of religious persecution in America involves the expulsion of Anne Hutchinson from Massachusetts Bay. While the case obviously antedates modern land use statutes, many of the elements are familiar. Apparently, Ms. Hutchinson attracted the disfavor of the establishment because she started holding regular sessions in her home to discuss (and criticize) sermons held in the dominant church. She started a women's club in her home to discuss the sermon and the Bible each week. The attendance at these meetings increased with the controversy over the banishment of Roger Williams. Women were attracted to Anne and wanted to hear her opinions. The first formal action taken against her was a resolution of the assembly in 1637, which, as reported by her principal antagonist, John Winthrop, read as follows:

That though women might meet (some few together) to pray and edify one another; yet such an assembly, (as was then the practice in Boston), where sixty or more did meet every week, and one woman (in a prophetical way, by resolving questions of doctrine, and expounding the scripture) took upon her the whole exercise, was agreed to be disorderly, and without rule.(see footnote 102)

In a modern setting, planning authorities would have complained of inadequate parking, traffic problems, and other signs of ''intensive'' land use. A sanction as austere as formal banishment in seventeenth-century New England would have been an unlikely, but modern authorities might have proven just as adept at finding a neutral rubric (here, ''disorderly conduct'') to exclude an unpopular religious activity.

 Page 221       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    The field of land use is particularly vital for the simple reason that religious activity, particularly the communal life of a religious group, necessarily involves using land. To some extent, this simply states the obvious, but some detail about the nature of religious land use in the United States may be helpful. The 1994 Report on the Survey of Religious Organizations at the National Level (the ''Survey''), conducted by the Northwestern University Survey Laboratory and the DePaul Law School's Center for Church/State Studies (with which I am involved), surveyed approximately 300 religious denominations in the United States, including virtually all major denominations.(see footnote 103) It found that nearly all religious organizations hold religious gatherings at least once a week. Not surprisingly, 96% of the respondents indicated that religious gatherings are held at a single permanent location. 89% of those utilizing such structures own them outright; 11% of respondents indicated that structures are leased.(see footnote 104) In addition, ''approximately two-thirds . . . engage in social service or welfare activities; over 80% are involved in education;(see footnote 105) nearly 60% provide recreation or social activities;(see footnote 106) 85% are involved in communications;(see footnote 107) one-third have retreat centers; and 40% have cemeteries.''(see footnote 108) These figures do not reflect the number of religious associations that operate hospitals or other health care facilities, nor do they reflect a variety of other programs carried out by religious social services agencies. 54% of the respondents indicate that their national bodies own real property that is not used for worship purposes, as do the local units of 54% of the respondents.(see footnote 109) Educational facilities and clergy housing are the most commonly held non-worship properties.(see footnote 110) In addition, approximately one-fifth of the organizations surveyed indicate that they invest in real estate to raise funds.(see footnote 111)
 Page 222       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    For the most part, the government officials dealing with land use issues in the nearly 70,000 local government entities of the United States are tolerant and respectful of religious rights. Nonetheless, particularly when community opposition is strong, or when the fashionable orthodoxies of the planning or historic preservation worlds are challenged, problematic instances occur.

    It is difficult to measure with precision the extent to which intentional religious discrimination plays a role in the problematic cases. As noted in In re American Friends of the Society of St. Pius v. Schwab, 417 N.Y.S.2d 991, 993 (N.Y. App. Div. 1979),

Human experience teaches us that public officials, when faced with pressure to bar church uses by those residing in a residential neighborhood, tend to avoid any appearance of an antireligious stance and temper their decision by carefully couching their grounds for refusal to permit such use in terms of traffic dangers, fire hazards and noise and disturbance, rather than on such crasser grounds as lessening of property values or loss of open space or entry of strangers into the neighborhood or undue crowding of the area. Under such circumstances it is necessary to most carefully scrutinize the reasons advanced for a denial to insure that they are real and not merely pretexts used to preclude the exercise of constitutionally protected privileges.

Despite such instinctive efforts on the parts of governing bodies to avoid the appearance of intolerance, I have absolutely no doubt that prejudice is a substantial factor in a large number of cases, particularly where smaller or less popular groups are involved.

 Page 223       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    Strong evidence for this conclusion is provided by a study I prepared with colleagues from the B.Y.U. Law School and at the law firm of Mayer, Brown & Platt in January, 1997. A copy of the study is attached as an appendix to my statement. Essentially, the study reviewed all the reported cases we were able to identify involving free exercise challenges to land use regulation. If anything, it seems reasonable to assume that these cases significantly understate the number of situations in which religious groups believe that their religious rights are being violated. A variety of practical disincentives—ranging from the need to have good working relationships with local officials and neighbors, to religiously based impulses to go the second mile, to the sheer cost of litigation, to the availability of other sites and the unattractiveness of settling among manifestly prejudiced neighbors—all operate to deter religious groups from over-litigating their claims.

    Cases were classified into two broad categories, essentially to see if there are significant differences between new construction situations (''location cases'') and cases dealing with whether an accessory use (such as a homeless shelter or soup kitchen) may be allowed at the site of an existing church (''accessory use cases''). The cases were also classified by denomination, to the extent that is possible based on case name or other information in the body of the decision. Information on size of denomination was based on data from a massive study that provides the best available estimates of church affiliation based on self-described affiliation.

    With this data in hand, we proceeded to compare the treatment received by smaller religious groups (those with 1.5% of the population or less) with that received by larger groups.(see footnote 112) If land use laws were being applied in a neutral fashion, one would expect roughly equal treatment. But in fact, the situation is quite different. Minority religions representing less than 9% of the population were involved in over 49% of the cases regarding the right to locate religious buildings at a particular site, and in over 33% of the cases seeking approval of accessory uses. The disproportionate burden becomes even more distressing if one takes into account smaller non-denominational or other unclassified groups. If these are counted, over 68% of reported location cases, and over 50% of accessory use cases, involve smaller religious groups.
 Page 224       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    While a study of this type can at best give a rough picture of what is happening, the conclusion seems inescapable that illicit motivationis affecting disputes in the land use area. Such illicit motivation may be present either in the form of prejudice against unpopular or less known groups, or in the form of undue favoring of more powerful groups, or most likely, both. There may of course be other factors that explain some of the disparity, but the differences are so staggering that it is virtually impossible to imagine that religious discrimination is not playing a significant role.

    Significantly, the judicial success rate for small religious groups and larger groups is essentially the same. The smaller groups won approximately 66% of the cases in which they were involved, whereas larger religious groups won approximately 65% of the cases in which they figured. These figures suggest that judicial review has on balance tended to help smaller religious groups. At the same time, they indicate that judicial decisions tend to be more impartial across groups, and that there is no reason to think the high proportion of disputes involving smaller religious groups reflects higher levels of ungrounded claims.

    The magnitude of the problem is reinforced when one considers that the reported cases are only the tip of the iceberg, since for the reasons discussed above, most religious groups bend over backwards to avoid conflicts with future neighbors and city officials they must deal with on a continuing basis. That is, religious groups are much more likely to give up on claims they may believe are valid in the interest of social peace than they are to litigate questionable claims aggressively. If anything, then, the study, with whatever unavoidable imperfections it may have, significantly understates the problems religious groups face.

 Page 225       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    Note that while the problems for smaller religious groups are particularly acute, the burdens faced by larger groups are not insignificant. A recent survey commissioned by the Presbyterian Church USA—a mainline denomination by anyone's definition—noted that 23% of its congregations had needed to obtain some sort of land use permit since January 1, 1992. Significant conflicts with city/county staff, neighbors, commission members, or others were encountered with respect to 10% of the land use approvals thus needed, although only 1% of the approvals needed have thus far been denied (with 4% remaining unresolved).(see footnote 113)

    The patterns of discrimination suggested by the foregoing statistics are all too familiar to those working in the religious land use area. In case after case, the plaintiff is a religious group that has obtained options on lot after lot, or has actually purchased a succession of lots, often after preliminary consultations with city officials, only to have a zoning request, a conditional use permit, a variance, or some other land use approval denied as opposition from local citizens climbs. Such denials are often issued even though similar religious uses from larger religious groups have been approved. This is exactly what happened when The Church of Jesus Christ of Latter-day Saints sought a zoning change for a temple site in Forest Hills Tennessee, as described in detail by Von Keetch in an earlier Congressional hearing held on March 26, 1998.(see footnote 114) Such denials are also a familiar litany in many cases involving Jehovah's Witnesses. And they are an even greater problem for newer or non-Christian religious groups.

    The facts of discrimination were particularly blatant in Islamic Center of Mississippi, Inc. v. City of Starkville, 840 F.2d 293 (5th Cir. 1988). A Muslim group that served primarily students at the University of Mississippi in Starkville sought necessary approvals for a place of worship near campus. Unfortunately, Starkville's zoning ordinance prohibited the use of buildings as churches in all the areas within the city limits that were near campus, and there was no place in the city in which worship facilities were permitted as of right. The Islamic Center considered three successive lots as possible worship sites, but each time was told by the City's building codes official that the sites could not be approved, either because of inadequate parking, heavy traffic on an adjacent street, or the risk of traffic congestion. The leaders then met with the building code official, and asked ''exactly where we can locate,'' and were told that a fourth location would be excellent, if sufficient parking was provided. The representatives of the Center then bought the property, and provided 18 on-site parking spaces. The planning commission recommended approval. Ultimately, however, the use had to be approved by the Board of Aldermen, and despite recommendations of approval from staff, the Board denied the approval when a neighbor claimed that the use would cause ''congestion, parking, and traffic problems.'' The Board thereupon denied the exception to the zoning ordinance that was sought. Subsequently some city officials inspected the building for conformity with fire and electrical requirements, and approved its conformity for worship. But several months later, in response to complaints about worship activities, the City ordered the Islamic Center to stop holding worship services at its building. What made this whole course of action particularly galling was that there was a residence next door that was used as a worship center for Pentecostal Christians. This group caused more noise, provided less parking and in general seemed less deserving of a zoning exception than Islamic Center. Five more churches were located within a quarter mile of the Center. The District Court, after holding that ''congregational prayer for Muslims is desirable, but not mandatory,'' and that the ''Starkville city ordinance does not preclude students from purchasing cars and driving to a worship site located [outside Starkville's city limits],'' concluded that
 Page 226       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

[s]tanding alone, the denial of the . . . [Center's] zoning application is not enough upon which to base an inference of discrimination. . . . The actions of the Board were supported by valid traffic considerations, and there is no evidence to suggest that it improperly considered plaintiffs' religion in reaching its decision.

Therefore, it held, the zoning ordinance did not violate the Islamic student's rights to free exercise of religion or substantive due process.(see footnote 115)

    Fortunately, the Circuit Court reversed, applying a heightened scrutiny test to reject the District Court's wooden deference to blatantly discriminatory state action and its decision that Starkville's zoning ordinance did not burden the Islamic students' free exercise rights. The Fifth Circuit Court rightly compared the comments about how poor Islamic students could simply buy cars to drive to church across town or outside the city limits to ''Anatole France's comment on the majestic equality of the law that forbids all men, the rich as well as the poor, to sleep under bridges. . . .''(see footnote 116)

    The difficulty is that in far too many cases, as noted in the Schwab case quoted above, land use decisions are wrapped in neutral sounding language about parking, setbacks, traffic impacts, and the like, which may constitute substantial and tangible harm to surrounding property owners, but in too many cases merely serves as an empty verbal mask hiding illicit discriminatory conduct aimed at the exercise of religion. Thus, lack of parking facilities that results in constant overparking of a narrow street, disrupting traffic and blocking neighboring driveways may constitute a genuine problem, but it does not justify excluding a religious use from an area if adequate on-site parking is provided (as was the case in Islamic Center) or if the religious use is needed at the location in question precisely because of religious requirements that participants must walk to the service.(see footnote 117) References to increased traffic flows may constitute a genuine risk to safety, or they may simply reflect moderate increases as likely to result without the religious use. Rigid insistence on setback or bulk requirements may be unnecessary, or may reflect an aesthetic concern that should give way to weightier religious freedom concerns. Building code problems may constitute substantial health and safety risks, or they may relate to matters that are routinely waived in a community.
 Page 227       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    The point is that land use provisions, while often assumed to be part of general and neutral regulatory schemes, characteristically involve permit schemes analogous to those struck down in Cantwell v. Connecticut,(see footnote 118) which granted local officials essentially standardless discretion to determine whether religious practices may go forward. Land use decisions are often delivered in conclusory language that can mask behind-the-scenes prejudice. Constitutional rights to the free exercise of religion are of little practical value if they permit control of the meeting place of a church to pass from its members to government outsiders without any examination of the government's asserted need for such control. Yet unless the goals of land use authorities are tested against more searching scrutiny than that provided by standards of neutrality and general applicability, agency officials have no occasion and no motivation to consider and weigh their regulatory objectives against the substantial burdens these may impose on the free exercise of religion. As the Supreme Court noted in Church of Lukumi Babalu Aye v. City of Hialeah,(see footnote 119) ''The Free Exercise Clause protects against governmental hostility which is masked as well as overt. 'The Court must survey meticulously the circumstances of governmental categories to eliminate, as it were, religious gerrymanders.' ''

    Significantly, the Supreme Court's decision in Smith jettisons strict scrutiny only as to neutral and generally applicable laws. As was clear even before Smith made the fact relevant, ''[z]oning laws are peculiar in that they are not really laws of general applicability but are, rather, linked to individual properties.''(see footnote 120) Some courts have built on this fact to hold that strict scrutiny continues to apply in the land use area as a reasonable construction of language in the Smith decision explicitly designed to avoid overturning Sherbert and its progeny. Thus, in First Covenant Church v. Seattle,(see footnote 121) the Washington Supreme Court found that a landmark designating ordinance was not general, because its criteria for application necessitated individual evaluations of each potential landmark property and was not neutral because of an exception for liturgy-based structural changes,(see footnote 122) and hence that the challenged ordinance failed under strict scrutiny. The court in First United Methodist Church of Seattle v. Seattle Landmarks Preservation Board,(see footnote 123) reached a similar conclusion, holding that while a particular church could be landmarked, it would violate the free exercise clause to allow restrictive features of the landmarking ordinance to be enforced so long as the building remained devoted to religious uses. While all courts have not reached the same conclusion,(see footnote 124) Congress may legitimately exercise its power under Section 5 of the 14th Amendment to remedy violations and to assure protection of free exercise values that remain protected under the reasonable interpretation of Smith advanced by the Washington cases.
 Page 228       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    One of the major problems in the land use area is that the public officials charged with enforcing them are all too prone to undervalue the concrete needs of religious activity as opposed to the other planning and preservation values. In part this is a reflection of what I called ''secular blindness'' or ''secular myopia'' above, and in part, it is a natural corollary of the commitment of such officials to planning and preservation values that motivated them to assume planning or preservation responsibilities in their communities in the first place. In the preservation context, the historical value of churches is sometimes given priority over the practical needs of living religion. In the planning context, idealized notions of the aesthetics and logic of urban layout are given greater credence than the need to allow land uses that can accommodate the needs of religious groups who desire to locate in a community and that will be as workable for the religious community as for residential neighborhoods and other more powerful blocs of the citizenry. The underlying values involved cannot be adequately balanced if any land use regulations the relevant authorities happen to prefer are determined to be ''neutral and general'' laws virtually immune to any religious freedom challenge.

    If courts are not authorized to invoke the kind of heightened scrutiny called for by the Religious Liberty Protection Act, it seems highly plausible to expect that the plight of minority religious groups documented above will further deteriorate, because courts will not be able to be as effective in rectifying the problems encountered by smaller groups as they have been in the past. In the absence of such heightened scrutiny, courts will have a much more difficult time unmasking discriminatory conduct and a much stricter obligation to be deferential to land use authorities. Ironically, this could lead to a situation in the future in which the disparity between reported land use cases of larger and smaller groups is reduced, not because the smaller groups believe their rights are being vindicated, but because they perceive the prospects of vindicating those claims in court are hopeless, and therefore cease bringing cases in the future that they might have pursued in the past.
 Page 229       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    The Religious Liberty Protection Act is well designed to remedy the types of problems identified by the analysis of reported land use cases submitted herewith, and made more concrete by consideration of the various cases discussed above. By focusing on laws which ''substantially burden religious exercise'', the Act avoids the risk of imposing unreasonable constraints on governmental action that might result if every type of state action that incidentally burdens religion could be challenged under the Act. At the same time, because ''religious exercise'' is defined to mean ''an act or refusal to act that is substantially motivated by a religious belief, whether or not the act or refusal is compulsory or central to a larger system of religious belief,'' it follows Smith in insisting that state agencies should not get into the business of assessing what is central to a religion. The insistence that land use authorities use the ''least restrictive means'' available to promote their policies is only reasonable: continuing to insist on a more burdensome course of action when a reasonable alternative is available transforms what may initially have been inadvertent discrimination into knowing and thus intentional imposition of an injury to religious sensitivities. Finally, the insistence on ''substantial and tangible harm'' provides a meaningful standard (and one that is as precise as the subject matter allows) for assuring that only genuinely significant land use concerns will be able to override religious liberty claims. Significantly, this standard does recognize that there are circumstances where land use regulations will be sufficiently significant to override religious concerns. Where a community can demonstrate ''substantial and tangible harm,'' a community may enforce land use regulations that will substantially burden religious exercise. However, in accordance with prior law, a community may not totally deprive a religious community of ''a reasonable location in the jurisdiction,'' and it may not deprive religious assemblies of equal access to areas where non-religious assemblies are permitted.

 Page 230       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    The highly individualized processes of land use regulation readily lend themselves to discrimination that is difficult or impossible to prove in individual cases, but which is in fact pervasive, as the study submitted herewith demonstrates. RLPA will help remedy this problem in part by adjusting burdens of proof. Moreover, the heightened scrutiny of land use regulation called for in the Act will be an important tool in helping to root out such discrimination. Congress has power under Section 5 of the Fourteenth Amendment to support remedial legislation of this type. Significantly, Sections 3(b)(1)(B) and (C) are sustainable for independent reasons. Section 3(b)(1)(B) codifies the rule that it is unconstitutional wholly to exclude First Amendment activity from a jurisdiction.(see footnote 125) If this principle were not sound, religious communities would be afforded less protection against land use authorities than adult theaters, bookstores, and other similar businesses. Section 3(b)(1)(C) codifies the rule that discrimination between different categories of speech, and particularly between differing viewpoints, and applies it to disallow land use regulations that might otherwise permit secular assemblies while excluding religious assemblies.

    Of course, religious discrimination does not lurk behind every land use decision, but this is not the requirement. Boerne allows assertion of Congressional power in contexts where ''there is reason to believe that many of the laws affected by the Congressional enactment have a significant likelihood of being unconstitutional.''(see footnote 126) Without remedial action, the pattern of discrimination evidenced by the study submitted herewith is all too likely to continue. Thus, Congress has power to enact the land use provisions of the Religious Liberty Protection Act.

III. COMMERCE POWER PROVIDES INDEPENDENT GROUNDS FOR ENACTING RLPA.

 Page 231       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    Before concluding, let me make a few final remarks regarding Commerce Power. At the outset, I wish to emphasize that in what follows I do not maintain that religious activity and commercial activity should be confused. Religious activity is not commerce, and even in the absence of First Amendment constraints, would not be regulable as commerce.

    Having said this, however, no one can doubt that religious activity substantially affects interstate commerce. Much more extensive documentation of this fact has been provided in particular by the Statement of Marc Stern at this Hearing. My aim is merely to note a few examples that suggest the extraordinary range of effects that religious activity in the land use area has on commerce.

    Land use regulations affect whether or not new religious buildings can be constructed. Religious institutions spend large amounts to build and maintain facilities for worship and for a variety of religiously motivated collateral activities, such as the provision of education, health care, recreational facilities and so forth.

    Many religious organizations are interstate and indeed international organizations. The DePaul Survey cited above indicates that while approximately 60% of the denominational respondents indicate that final decisions as to location and property acquisition are made at the local level, nearly 20% indicated that such decisions are made by state, regional, or national bodies.(see footnote 127) This means that for a substantial number of religious organizations, decisions regarding church building and expansion are made in one state and implemented in another. Funds typically flow in interstate commerce from one location to another in support of these objectives.

 Page 232       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    In some ecclesiastical polities, funds are collected and retained at the local level, but in others, they are gathered, transferred electronically to a central location, and then distributed back out nationally or internationally in accordance with the needs of various congregations. Charitable aid flowing through these channels depends to some extent on where congregations are ultimately located. Even where facilities are leased, the funds involved often flow in interstate commerce. Local as well as national organizations often own retreat facilities which may be located at a distance, even in a different state. Many religious organizations undertake humanitarian aid projects that involve sending goods (e.g., clothing) and services (e.g., medical aid) across state and international boundaries. Land use regulations impeding such uses obviously regulate activity that substantially affects interstate commerce.

    City regulation of religious land use has the potential to divert the flow of commerce from one state to another. Certainly, it often impedes the flow, for substantial periods, while churches administered nationally look for alternative sites. The L.D.S. Church currently builds 300–400 churches annually. The cost of such buildings typically runs into the multimillion dollar range. Approximately half of these are built in various states of the United States, and the remainder are located internationally. This experience must be multiplied by that of hundreds of other denominations in the United States. Land-use regulations unquestionably delay or block such religious activity, with direct negative impacts on commerce that would otherwise occur.

    Some religious facilities may attract believers to travel across state lines to regional retreat or worship facilities. Temples have this characteristic for believing Mormons; countless other churches have similar structures. Retreat, camp, or recreational facilities may lie across state lines. The location of a new church building in a municipality will typically result in a new flow of literature, media items, computers, and other such matters, as well as the installation of new interstate telephone lines and other means of communication. Often, supervisory personnel will need to travel to assure that new construction is handled properly and that existing facilities are properly maintained. These are precisely the types of activity that have justified Congressional regulation in the interest of civil rights in other contexts.(see footnote 128)
 Page 233       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    All too frequently, the current land use regime operates as a kind of non-tariff trade barrier against new and less popular religious groups, with ripple impacts on all the other types of commerce that the new religious activity would otherwise stimulate. Moreover, as noted above, current administration of land use rules creates in effect an unfairly burdensome excessive market for real estate options, as the sorry experience of numerous religious groups in proffering site after site to local planning authorities confirms. Congress can legitimately determine that it will regulate a field (or occupy a field with non-regulation) where it desires to assure that activities substantially affecting commerce (here: religious activities) should not be burdened, or should be burdened only where there are strong and non-discriminatory grounds for the burden.

    Examples could be multiplied, but what has been said amply supports the truly massive impact religious activity in general, and more particularly, religious activity directly impacted by land use regulation, has on interstate commerce. Particularly when replicated across denominations and across the thousands of municipalities in the United States, the substantial effect on commerce is undeniable. Eliminating unjustified burdens on religious exercise will promote commerce, and justifies Congressional intervention to assure that religious activity and its substantial affects on commerce is not unfairly burdened by differential land use regimes around the country.

APPENDIX

Discrimination Against Minority Churches in Zoning Cases

 Page 234       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    In order to gain some perspective on the treatment of non-mainline groups in zoning cases, a broad sample of zoning decisions challenged on free exercise grounds has been analyzed. A total of 196 cases was ultimately included in the study. This set of cases should include a fairly comprehensive set of reported cases in this field. It includes all cases cited in annotations that have collected cases on this topic (including cases cited in pocket part updates),(see footnote 129) all cases cited in the section of a leading treatise on zoning that addresses issues of religious land uses,(see footnote 130) and all cases identified through a Westlaw search classified under West's Constitutional Law Key Number 84.5(18), which collects religion cases involving zoning and land use. It is conceivable that some cases involving religion-based constitutional challenges to zoning decisions may not have been captured through these sources, but it is unlikely that there are many such cases.

    The cases thus collected have been classified by the type of zoning case and by the denomination involved. Essentially, the zoning issues fall into two broad categories: cases that involve zoning on property to permit a church building to be erected on a particular site (''location cases''), and cases that determine whether an accessory use (such as a homeless shelter or soup kitchen) may be allowed at the site of an existing church (''accessory use cases'').

    In most of the cases, the denomination involved is obvious either from the case name or from discussion of the case in the opinion. There are, however, a substantial number of cases in which either no denominational affiliation appears in the case, or the church involved is non-denominational. These cases are designated as ''unclassified'' in the tables below. While some of the unclassified religious associations may in fact have a denominational affiliation that simply is not evident from the cases, most of these cases appear to involve local, congregationally organized churches that are functionally similar to the organizations we have classified as minority churches.
 Page 235       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Information on the size of various denominations was derived from tables provided in BARRY A. KOSMIN &CONTEMPORARY AMERICAN SOCIETY 15–17 (1993). The data is derived from the National Survey of Religious Identification conducted by the Graduate School of the City University of New York, which surveyed a representative sample of 113,000 people across the continental United States. This is the most comprehensive poll ever conducted on the issue of religious affiliation. Id. at 1–2. It provides the best available data of religious affiliation as assessed from the perspective of the believer.

    The line between mainline denominations and smaller groups is difficult to draw, because one is dealing with a continuum. For purposes of this study, groups with more than 1.5% of the adult population were treated as mainline groups, whereas groups with smaller percentages were included in the minority category. The only exception in the tables that follow is Judaism, but if the statistics on Judaism were divided to reflect the major branches of that tradition, the various branches would come under the 1.5% threshold. Some smaller Protestant groups may be more analogous to mainline groups, so that the categorizations in a few cases could be questioned.

    The population percentages in the tables that follow do not add up to 100% because the tables do not include data on non-religious groups and on the portion of the population (only 2.30%) that did not respond to the survey. Many smaller religions were not covered by the study because they have no reported cases, but such religions represent only 2.22% of the population.

 Page 236       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    In analyzing the data, a basic starting assumption is that any zoning dispute that progresses far enough into litigation to yield a reported decision reflects a situation in which religious groups perceive that their religious rights are being violated. For a variety of practical reasons, ranging from the need to have a good working relationship with local government officials to the sheer cost of litigation to the availability of alternative sites, churches probably bring fewer actions in this area than they think they may be entitled to bring. Table 1 summarizes the number of cases in the location and accessory use categories by denomination:

Table 2

    The figures indicated in Table 1 already suggest that a substantial amount of the litigation in this area involves minority religious groups. This burden is more pronounced when compared to the percentage of groups from these denominations in the general population. Table 2 provides these comparisons.

Table 3



    The data in Table 2 are not wholly satisfactory, because the relative populations of various religious groups vary over the rather lengthy period from which the cases are drawn, whereas the population figures, to the extent they are available, are quite recent. Nonetheless, the figures suffice to give a rough sense for how the percentage of cases in which a given religious society is involved corresponds with that society's percentage representation in the population as a whole. These figures strongly suggest that a high percentage of cases are being contested by religious groups comprising a very small percentage of the total population.

Table 4

    According to Table 3, 63% of religious claims were granted, and 37% were denied. At the judicial level, minority groups appear to fare slightly better than mainline groups: they won 57 cases, or 66% of the cases in which they were involved; majority religions prevailed in 26 cases, or 65% of the cases in which they were involved. Among other things, these figures suggest that judicial review does help remedy the problems minority groups face, and tends to be impartial across groups. Since the data do not indicate that the higher percentage of cases in which minority religions are involved reflect higher levels of ungrounded claims, Table 2's data showing that minority groups face a substantially greater level of problems in the zoning area than mainline churches seems sound.
 Page 237       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    The percentage of cases in which various denominations' religious challenges to zoning decisions have been won and lost is summarized in Table 4. The figures show the number of claims won and lost both as percentages of the total number of cases and as percentages of the total number of claims in which each denomination (or group of denominations) is involved.

Table 5

    The foregoing data suggest that a variety of factors are operating in the zoning area in the United States that lead to de facto discrimination against smaller religious groups. This confirms that behind the surface of ostensibly neutral zoning laws, a variety of discriminatory and prejudicial factors may be operational that have the effect of violating the religious rights of minority groups.

    To facilitate access to the date provided in this appendix, the cases reviewed are listed below, classified as they have been categorized in the study. Within each denominational category, the citations appear alphabetically by jurisdiction (with federal cases preceding state cases) in reverse chronological order. The parenthetical following the citations includes how the case was classified for purposes of the study. The letters in the parentheticals have the following meanings:

G = The religious organization prevailed on the religious claim asserted.
D = The religious claim asserted was denied.
L = The case was a ''location'' case.
A = The case was an ''accessory use'' case.
 Page 238       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

CATHOLIC:

Keeler v. Mayor & City Council of Cumberland, 940 F. Supp. 879 (D. Md. 1996) (D) (A)

Ellsworth v. Gercke, 156 P.2d 242 (Ariz. 1945) (G) (L)

Ramona Convent of Holy Names v. City of Alhambra, 26 Cal. Rptr. 2d 140 (Ct. App. 1993) (D) (A)

Tustin Heights Ass'n v. Board of Supervisors of County of Orange, 339 P.2d 914 (Cal. Dist. Ct. App. 1959) (D) (L)

St. John's Roman Catholic Church Corp. v. Town of Darien, 184 A.2d 42 (Conn. 1959) (D) (L)

Daughters of St. Paul v. Zoning Board, 549 A.2d 1076 (Conn. App. Ct. 1988) (G) (A)

Hull v. Miami Shores Village, 435 So.2d 868 (Fla. Dist. Ct. App. 1983) (D) (A)

Diakonian Soc'y v. City of Chicago, 380 N.E.2d 843 (Ill. App. Ct. 1978) (G) (L)
 Page 239       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

Board of Zoning Appeals v. Wheaton, 76 N.E.2d 597 (Ind. Ct. App. 1948) (G) (A)

Society of Jesus of New England v. Boston Landmarks Comm'n, 564 N.E.2d 571 (Mass. 1990) (G) (L)

Sisters of Holy Cross of Mass. v. Town of Brookline, 198 N.E.2d 624 (Mass. 1964) (G) (L)

Mooney v. Village of Orchard Lake, 53 N.W.2d 308 (Mich. 1952) (G) (L)

City of Minneapolis v. Church Universal & Triumphant, 339 N.W.2d 880 (Minn. 1983) (G) (L)

Association for Educ. Dev. v. Hayward, 533 S.W.2d 579 (Mo. 1976) (G) (A)

Black v. Town of Montclair, 167 A.2d 388 (N.J. 1961) (G) (A)

Andrews v. Board of Adjustment, 143 A.2d 262 (N.J. Super. Ct. Law Div. 1958) (G) (A)

Diocese of Rochester v. Planning Board, 136 N.E.2d 827 (N.Y. 1956) (G) (L)

Diocese of Buffalo v. Buckowski, 446 N.Y.S.2d 1015 (Sup. Ct. 1982) (D) (L)
 Page 240       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

Province of Meribah Soc'y of Mary, Inc. v. Village of Muttontown, 538 N.Y.S.2d 850 (App. Div. 1989) (D) (A)

American Friends of Soc'y of St. Pius, Inv. v. Schwab, 417 N.Y.S.2d 991 (App. Div. 1979) (G) (L)

People v. Kalayjiami, 352 N.Y.S. 2d 115 (App. Div. 1973) (D) (L)

Franciscan Missionaries of Mary v. Herdman, 184 N.Y.S.2d 104 (App. Div. 1959) (G) (A)

Hayes v. Fowler, 473 S.E.2d 442 (N.C. Ct. App. 1996) (G) (A)

Allen v. City of Burlington Board of Adjustment, 397 S.E.2d 657 (N.C. Ct. App. 1990) (G) (L)

Archdiocese v. Washington County, 458 P.2d 682 (Or. 1969) (D) (L)

O'Hara v. Board of Adjustment, 131 A.2d 587 (Pa. 1957) (D) (L)

Stark's Appeal, 72 Pa D. & C. 1681 (Pa. 1950) (G) (A)

In re Appeal of Hoffman, 444 A.2d 764 (Pa. Commw. Ct. 1982) (G) (A)

 Page 241       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
State ex rel. Roman Catholic Bishop v. Hill, 90 P.2d 217 (Nev. 1939) (G) (L)

MAJOR PROTESTANT:

BAPTIST:

Messiah Baptist Church v. County of Jefferson, 859 F.2d 820 (10th Cir. 1988) (D) (L)

Messiah Baptist Church v. County of Jefferson, 697 F.Supp. 396 (D. Colo. 1987) (D) (L)

Ex Parte Fairhope Bd. of Adjustments, 567 So.2d 1353 (Ala. 1990) (D) (A)

Corinth Baptist Church v. State Dep't of Transp., 656 So.2d 868 (Ala. Civ. Ct. App. 1995 (D) (A)

Cochise County v. Broken Arrow Baptist Church, 778 P.2d 1302 (Ariz. Ct. App. 1989) (D) (L)

Abram v. City of Fayetteville, 661 S.W.2D 371 (ARK. 1983) (D) (A)

City of Chico v. First Ave. Baptist Church, 238 P.2d 587 (Cal. Dist. Ct. App. 1951) (D) (L)

 Page 242       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
East Side Baptist Church of Denver v. Klein, 487 P.2d 549 (Colo. 1971) (D) (A)

Parkview Baptist Church v. City of Pueblo, 336 P.2d 310 (Colo. 1959) (D) (A)

North Syracuse First Baptist Church v. Village of N. Syracuse, 524 N.Y.S.2d 894 (App. Div. 1988) (G) (A)

Yocum v. Power, 157 A.2d 368 (Pa. 1960) (G) (L)

Antrim Faith Baptist Church v. Commonwealth, 460 A.2D 1228 (PA. COMMW. CT. 1983) (D) (L)

City of Sumner v. First Baptist Church, 639 P.2d 1358 (Wash. 1982) (G) (A)

State ex rel. Lake Drive Baptist Church v. Bayside Bd. of Trustees, 108 N.W.2d 288 (Wis.) (G) (L)

EPISCOPAL:

Rector, Wardens, & Members of Vestry of St. Bartholomew's Church v. City of New York, 914 F.2d 348 (2d Cir. 1990) (G) (A)

O'Brien v. Chicago, 105 N.E.2d 917 (Ill. App. Ct. 1952) (G) (L)

 Page 243       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
State v. Cameron, 498 A.2d 1217 (N.J. 1985) (G) (L)

Greentree at Murray Hill Condominiums v. Good Shepherd Episcopalian Church, 550 N.Y.S.2d 981 (Sup. Ct. 1989) (G) (A)

Diocese of Central New York v. Schwarzer, 199 N.Y.S.2d 939 (Sup. Ct. 1960) (G) (L)

Heard v. City of Dallas, 456 S.W.2d 440 (Tex. Civ. app. Ct. 1970) (G) (L)

LUTHERAN:

Miami Beach Lutheran Church of Epiphany v. City of Miami Beach, 82 So.2d 880 (Fla. 1955) (D) (L)

Johnson v. Evangelical Lutheran Church of Messiah, 54 S.E.2d 722 (Ga. Ct. App. 1949) (G) (L)

Bethel Evangelical Lutheran Church v. Village of Morton, 559 N.E.2d 533 (Ill. App. Ct. 1990) (D) (A)

Our Savior's Evangelical Lutheran Church of Naperville v. City of Naperville, 542 N.E.2d 1158 (Ill. App. Ct. 1989) (G) (A)

Schueller v. Board of Adjustment, 95 N.W.2d 731 (Iowa 1959) (G) (L)
 Page 244       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

Zion Evangelical Lutheran Church v. City of Detroit Lakes, 21 N.W.2d 203 (Minn. 1945) (D) (L)

St. John's Evangelical Lutheran Church v. City of Hoboken, 479 A.2d 935 (N.J. Super. Ct. Law Div. 1983) (G) (L)

Lutheran in America v. City of New York, 316 N.E.2d 305 (N.Y. 1974) (G) (A)

Synod of Ohio of United Lutheran Church v. Joseph, 39 N.E.2d 515 (Ohio 1942) (G) (L)

METHODIST:

West Hartford Methodist Church v. Zoning Board of Appeals, 121 A.2d 640 (Conn. 1956) (D) (A)

Keeling v. Board of Zoning Appeals, 69 N.E.2d 613 (Ind. Ct. App. 1946( (G) (L)

Linden Methodist Episcopal Church v. Linden, 173 A. 593 (N.J. 1934) (G) (L)

Cash v. Brookshire Methodist Church, 573 N.E.2d 692 (Ohio Ct. App. 1988) (G) (A)

 Page 245       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
First United Methodist Church of Seattle v. Hearing Examiner for Seattle Landmarks Preservation Bd., 916 P.2d 374 (Wash. 1996) (G) (L)

PENTECOSTAL:

Pentecostal Holiness Church v. Dunn, 27 So.2d 561 (Ala. 1946 ) (G) (L)

PRESBYTERIAN:

Western Presbyterian Church. v. Board of Zoning Adjustment, 862 F.Supp 538 (D.D.C. 1994) (G) (A)

Synod of Chesapeake, Inc. v. City of Newark, 254 A.2d 611 (Del. Ch. 1969) (G) (A)

City of Richmond Heights v. Richmond Heights Presbyterian Church 764 S.W.2d 647 (Mo. 1989) (G) (A)

First Westminister Presbyterian Church v. City Council, 393 N.Y.S.2d 180 (App. Div. 1977) (G) (L)

Westminister Presbyterian Church v. Edgecomb, 189 N.W. 671 (1922) (G) (L)

MINORITY DENOMINATIONS:

 Page 246       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
ASSEMBLIES OF GOD:

First Assembly of God v. Collier County, 20 F.3d 419 (11th Cir. 1994) (D) (A)

First Assembly of God v. City of Alexandria, 739 F.2d 942 (4th Cir. 1984) (D) (A)

First Assembly of God v. Collier County, 775 F.Supp. 383 (M.D. Fla. 1991) (D) (A)

Lakeshore Assembly of God Church v. Village Board of Village of Westfield, 508 N.Y.S.2d 819 (App. Div. 1986) (D) (A)

BUDDHIST:

Moore v. Trippe, 743 F.Supp 201 (S.D.N.Y. 1990) (G) (A)

CHRISTIAN SCIENCE:

Bright Horizon House, Inc. v. Zoning Bd. of Appeals, 469 N.Y.S.2d 851 (Sup. Ct. 1983) (D) (L)

Mahart v. First Church of Christ Scientist, 142 N.E.2d 678 (Ohio Ct. App. 1955) (G) (A)
 Page 247       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

CHURCH OF CHRIST:

Church of Christ v. Metropolitan Bd. of Zoning Appeals, 371 N.E.2d 1331 (Ind. Ct. App. 1978) (G) (A)

CHURCH OF GOD:

Church of God v. City of Monroe, 404 F. Supp. 175 (M.D. La. 1975) (G) (A)

Jernigan v. Smith, 126 S.E.2d 678 (Ga. 1962) (D) (L)

City of Sherman v. Simms, 183 S.W.2d 415 (Tex. 1944) (D) (L)

State ex rel. Howell v. Meador, 154 S.E. 876 (W. Va. 1930) (G) (L)

THE CHURCH OF JESUS CHRIST OF LATTER-DAY SAINTS:

The Church of Jesus Christ of Latter-day Saints v. Jefferson County, 741 F. Supp 1522 (N.D. Ala 1990) (G) (L)

Corporation of the Presiding Bishop v. City of Porterville, 203 P.2d 823 (Cal. Dist. Ct. App. 1949) (D) (L)

Corporation of the Presiding Bishop v. Ashton, 448 P.2d 185 (Idaho 1968) (G) (A)
 Page 248       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

City of Las Cruces v. Huerta, 692 P.2d 1331 (N.M. Ct. App. 1984) (D) (L)

EASTERN ORTHODOX:

Macedonian Orthodox Church v. Planning Bd., 636 A.2d 96 (N.J. Super. Ct. App. Div. 1994) (D) (L)

Appeal of Russian Orthodox Church of Holy Ghost, 152 A.2d 489 (Pa. 1959) (D) (A)

EVANGELICAL:

State ex rel. Covenant Harbor Bible Camp v. Steinke, 96 N.W.2d 356 (Wis. 1959) (G) (L)

Cornerstone Bible Church v. City of Hastings, 740 F. Supp 654 (D. Minn. 1990) (D) (L)

HARE KRISHNA:

Marsland v. International Soc'y for Krishna Consciousness, 657 P.2d 1035 (Haw. 1983) (D) (L)

ISLAM:

 Page 249       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
Islamic Center v. City of Starkville, 840 F.2d 293 (5th Cir. 1988) (G) (L)

Islamic Soc'y v. Foley, 464 N.Y.S.2d 844 (App. Div. 1983) (G) (L)

JEHOVAH'S WITNESSES:

Lakewood, Ohio Congregation of Jehovah's Witnesses, Inc. v. City of Lakewood, 699 F.2d 303 (6th Cir. 1983) (D) (L)

Galfas v. City of Atlanta, 193 F.2d 931 (5th Cir. 1952) (D) (L)

Jehovah's Witnesses Assembly Halls v. Jersey City, 597 F. Supp 972 (D.N.J. 1984) (G) (L)

Matthews v. Board of Supervisors, 21 Cal Rptr. 914 (Dist. Ct. App. 1962) (D) (L)

Garden Grove Congregation of Jehovah's Witnesses v. Garden Grove, 1 Cal. Rptr. 65 (Dist. Ct. App. 1959) (D) (L)

Redwood City Co. of Jehovah's Witnesses v. City of Menlo Park, 335 P.2d 195 (Cal. Dist. Ct. App. 1959) (G) (L)

Minney v. City of Azusa, 330 P.2d 255 (Cal. Dist. Ct. App. 1958) (D) (L)

 Page 250       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
State ex rel. Tampa Co. of Jehovah's Witnesses v. City of Tampa, 48 So. 2d 78 (Fla. 1950) (G) (L)

Rogers v. Mayor of Atlanta, 137 S.E.2d 668, 672 (Ga. Ct. App. 1964) (G) (L)

Columbus Park Congregation of Jehovah's Witnesses, Inc. v. Board of Appeals, 182 N.E.2d 722 (Ill. 1962) (G) (L)

Board of Zoning Appeals v. Decatur Co. Jehovah's Witnesses, 117 N.E.2d 115 (Ind. 1954) (D) (A)

Minnetonka Congregation of Jehovah's Witnesses, Inc. v. Svee, 226 N.W.2d 306 (Minn. 1975) (G) (L)

Allendale Congregation of Jehovah's Witnesses v. Grosman, 152 A.2d 569 (N.J. 1959) (D) (L)

Jehovah's Witnesses Assembly Hall of S. New Jersey v. Woolwich Township, 532 A.2d 276 (N.J. Super. Ct. Law Div. 1987) (G) (L)

State ex rel. Wiegel v. Randall, 116 N.E.2d 300 (Ohio 1953) (G) (L)

Libis v. Board of Zoning Appeals, 292 N.E.2d 642 (Ohio Ct. App. 1972) (G) (L)

 Page 251       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
Milwaukie Co. of Jehovah's Witnesses v. Mullen, 330 P.2d 5 (Or. 1958) (D) (L)

Appeal of Trustees of the Congregation of Jehovah's Witnesses, 130 A.2d 240 (Pa. Super. Ct. 1957) (D) (L)

Congregation Comm. N. Fort Worth Congregation, Jehovah's Witnesses v. City Council, 287 S.W.2d 700 (Tex. Civ. App. Ct. 1956) (G) (L)

State ex rel. Wenatchee Congregation of Jehovah's Witnesses v. City of Wenatchee, 312 P.2d 195 (Wash. 1957) (G) (L)

JUDAISM:

Grosz v. City of Miami Beach, 721 F.2d 729 (11th Cir. 1983) (D) (L)

Village of Univ. Heights v. Cleveland Jewish Orphan's Home, 20 F.2d 743 (6th Cir. 1927) (G) (L)

Lucas Valley Homeowners Ass'n v. County of Marin, 284 Cal. Rptr. 427 (Ct. App. 1991) (G) (L)

Stoddard v. Edelman, 84 Cal. Rptr. 443 (Ct. App. 1970) (G) (L)

Beit Havurah v. Zoning Board of Appeals, 418 A.2d 82 (Conn. 1979) (G) (A)
 Page 252       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

Garbaty v. Norwalk Jewish Ctr., Inc., 171 A.2d 197 (Conn. 1961) (G) (L)

Lubavitch Chabad House v. City of Evanston, 445 N.E.2d 343 (Ill. App. Ct. 1982) (G) (L)

Wolbach v. Zoning Bd. of Appeals, 226 N.E.2d 679 (Ill. App. Ct. 1967) (G) (L)

Schwartz v. Congregation Powolei Zeduck, 131 N.E.2d 785 (Ill. App. Ct. 1956) (G) (L)

Congregation David Ben Nuchim v. City of Oak Park, 199 N.W.2d 557 (Mich. Ct. App. 1972) (G) (L)

Congregation Temple Israel v. City of Creve Coeur, 320 S.W.2d 451 (Mo. 1959) (G) (L)

Kali Bari Temple v. Board of Adjustment, 638 A.2d 839 (N.J. Super. Ct. App. Div. 1994) (G) (L)

Lakewood Residents Ass'n v. Congregation Zichron Schneur, 570 A.2d 1032 (N.J. Super. Ct. Law Div. 1989) (G) (L)

Farhi v. Commissioners of Borough of Deal, 499 A.2d 559 (N.J. Super. Ct. Law Div. 1985) (G) (L)
 Page 253       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

Sexton v. Bates, 85 A.2d 833 (N.J. Super. Ct. Law Div. 1951), aff'd sub nom., Sexton v. Essex County Ritualarium, 91 A.2d 162 (N.J. Super. Ct. App. Div. 1952) (D) (L)

Jewish Reconstructionalist Synagogue v. Village of Roslyn Harbor, 342 N.E.2d 534 (N.Y. 1975) (G) (L)

Westchester Reform Temple v. Brown, 239 N.E.2d 891 (N.Y. 1968) (G) (A)

Community Synagogue v. Bates, 136 N.E.2d 488 (N.Y. 1956)(G) (L)

Slevin v. Long Island Jewish Medical Ctr., 314 N.Y.S.2d 937 (Sup. Ct. 1971) (G) (A)

Westbury Hebrew Congregation, Inc. v. Downer, 59 Misc. 2d 387 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. 1969) (G) (A)

Westchester Reform Temple v. Griffin, 276 N.Y.W.2d 737 (Sup. Ct. 1966 (D) (A)

Application of Garden City Jewish Center, 155 N.Y.S.2d 523 (Sup. Ct. 1956 (G) (L)

Harrison Orothodox Minyan, Inc. v. Town Board, 552 N.Y.S.2d 434 (App. Div 1990) (G) (L)

 Page 254       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
Yeshiva and Mesivta Toras Chaim v. Rose, 523 N.Y.S.2d 907 (App. Div. 1989) (D) (L)

Siegert v. Luney, 491 N.Y.S.2d 15 (App. Div. 1985) (G) (A)

North Shore Hebrew Academy v. Wegman, 481 N.Y.S.2d 142 (App. Div. 1984) (G) (A)

Congregation Gates of Prayer v. Board of Appeals, 368 N.Y.S.2d 232 (App. Div. 1975) (D) (L)

Seaford Jewish Ctr., Inc. v. Board of Zoning Appeals, 368 N.Y.S.2d 40 (App. Div. 1975) (G) (L)

Ginsberg v. Yeshiva of Far Rockaway, 358 N.Y.S.2d 477 (App. Div. 1974) (D) (A)

Shaffer v. Temple Beth Emeth, 190 N.Y.S. 841 (App. Div. 1921) (G) (A)

Young Israel Org. v. Dworkin, 133 N.E.2d 174 (Ohio Ct. App. 1956) (G) (L)

Overbrook Farms Club v. Zoning Board, 40 A.2d 423 (Pa. 1945) (G) (A)

Appeal of Floersheim, 34 A.2d 62 (Pa. 1943) (G) (A)

 Page 255       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
Minyan v. Cheltenham Township, 552 A.2d 772 (Pa. Commw. Ct. 1989) (G) (L)

Berlant v. Zoning Hearing Board, 279 A.2d 400 (Pa. Commw. Ct. 1971) (G) (L)

State ex rel. B'Nai B'rith Foundation v. Walworth Co. Bd. of Adjustment, 208 N.W.2d 113 (Wis. 1973) (G) (L)

QUAKERS:

Milharcic v. Metropolitan Bd. of Zoning Appeals, 489 N.E.2d 634 (Ind. Ct. App. 1986) (G) (L)

SEVENTH DAY ADVENTISTS:

Application of Faith for Today, Inc., 204 N.Y.S.2d 751 (App. Div. 1960) (G) (L)

UNIFICATION CHURCH:

New Educ. Dev. Sys. Inc. v. Boitano, 573 F. Supp. 594 (N.D. Cal. 1983) (G) (L)

Holy Spirit Ass'n v. Town of New Castle, 480 F. Supp. 1212 (S.D.N.Y. 1979) (D) (L)

Holy Spirit Ass'n for Unification of World Christianity v. Brush, 469 N.Y.S.2d (App. Div. 1983) (G) (A)
 Page 256       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

UNITARIAN:

North Shore Unitarian Soc'y v. Village of Plandome, 109 N.Y.S.2d 803 (Sup. Ct. 1951) (G) (L)

Unitarian Universalist Church v. Shorten, 314 N.Y.S.2d 66 (Sup. Ct. 1970) (G) (A)

UNCLASSIFIED:

Cornerstone Bible Church v. City of Hastings, 948 F.2d 464 (8th Cir. 1991) (G) (L)

Christian Gospel Church, Inc. v. City & County of San Francisco, 896 F.2d 1221 (9th cir. 1990) (D) (L)

Daytona Rescue Mission, Inc. v. City of Daytona Beach, 885 F. Supp. 1554 (M.D. Fla. 1995) (D) (A)

Alpine Christian Fellowship v. County Comm'rs, 870 F. Supp. 991 (D. Colo. 1994) (Alpine Christian Fellowhip) (G) (A)

Nichols v. Planning & Zoning Comm'n, 667 F. Supp. 72 (D. Conn. 1987) (G) (L)

 Page 257       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
Love Church v. City of Evanston, 671 F. Supp. 508 (N.D. Ill. 1987) (D) (L)

Seward Chapel, Inc. v. City of Seward, 655 P.2d 1293 (Alaska 1982) (D) (A)

City of Colorado Springs v. Blanche, 761 P.2d 212 (Colo. 1988) (D) (L)

Grace Community Church v. Town of Bethel, 622 A.2d 591 (Conn. App. Ct. 1993) (G) (L)

Grace Community Church v. Planning Comm'n, 615 A.2d 1092 (Conn. Super. Ct. 1992) (G) (L)

Town v. Reno, 377 So. 2d 648 (Fla. 1979) (Ethiopian Zion Coptic Church) (D) (L)

Pylant v. Orange County, 328 So. 2d 199 (Fla. 1976) (First Apostolic) (D) (L)

State v. Maxwell, 617 P.2d 816 (Haw. 1980) (Hula Hau) (D) (A)

Hope Deliverance Ctr., Inc. v. Zoning Bd. of Appeals, 452 N.E.2d 630 (Ill. App. Ct. 1983) (Non-denominational) (G) (L)

South Side Move of God Church v. Zoning Bd. of Appeals, 365 N.E.2d 118 (Ill. App. Ct. 1977) (D) (A)
 Page 258       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

Twin-City Bible Church v. Zoning Board of Appeals, 365 N.E.2d 1381 (Ill. App. Ct. 1977) (G) (A)

Coston Chapel A.M.E. Church v. Chaddick, 292 N.E.2d 215 (Ill. App. Ct. 1972) (D) (L)

Family Christian Fellowship v. County of Winnebago, 503 N.E.2d 367 (Ill. App. Ct. 1986) (G) (L)

Board of Zoning Appeals v. New Testament Bible Church, 411 N.E.2d 681 (Ind. Ct. App. 1980) (G) (A)

Portage Township v. Full Salvation Union, 29 N.W.2d 297 (Mich. 1947) (D) (A)

Yanow v. Seven Oaks Park, A. 2d 482 (N.J. 1963) (Eastern Christian Institute) (D) (L)

Covenant Community Church, Inc. v. Gates Zoning Bd. of Appeals, 444 N.Y.S.2d 415 (Sup. Ct 1981) (G) (L)

Duallo Realty Corp. v. Silver, 224 N.Y.S. 2d 55 (Sup. Ct. 1965) (Temple Emanuel) (G) (A)

Holy Sepulchre Cemetary v. City of Greece, 191 Misc. 241 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. 1947) (D) (L)
 Page 259       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

Neddermeyer v. Town of Ontario Planning Bd., 548 N.Y.S. 2d 951 (App. Div. 1989) (The Healing Church) (G) (L)

Unification of World Christianity v. Rosenfeld, 458 N.Y.S. 2d 920 (App. Div. 1983) (Holy Spirit Ass'n) (D) (L)

Independent Church Realization of Word of God, Inc. v. Board of Zoning Appeals, 437 N.Y.S. 2d 443 (App. Div. 1981) (D) (L)

State ex rel. Anshe Chesed Congregation v. Bruggemeir, 115 N.E. 2d 65 (Ohio Ct. App. 1953) (Anshe Chesed Congregation) (G) (L)

Damascus Community Church v. Clackamus County, 610 P. 2d 273 (Or. Ct. App. 1980) (D) (A)

Christian Retreat Ctr. v. Board of County Comm'rs, 560 P. 2d 1100 (Or. Ct. App. 1977) (D) (A)

Church of Savior v. Zoning Hearing Bd., 568 A.2d 1336 (Pa. Commw. Ct. 1989) (G) (L)

Conversion Center, Inc. v. Zoning Board of Adjustment, 278 A.2d 369 (Pa. Commw. Ct. 1971) (G) (L)

 Page 260       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
City of Rapid City v. Kahler, 334 N.W.2d 510 (S.D. 1983) (Conerston Rescue Mission) (G) (L)

Fountain Gate Ministries, Inc. v. City of Plano, 654 S.W.2d 841 (Tex. Ct. App. 1983) (D) (A)

First Covenant Church v. City of Seattle, 840 P.2d 174 (Wash. 1992) (G) (L)

    Mr. CANADY. Mr. Scott.

    Mr. SCOTT. Thank you, Mr. Chairman.

    Mr. Mauck, when discussing discrimination against religions, why can't the civil rights statutes be amended to just add or enforce religious bigotry without a new area of the law?

    Mr. MAUCK. All of the ordinances that I have ever seen treat churches as a separate land use category. The ordinances themselves are seeing land uses in a religious way, and they need to be addressed. Racial discrimination is hard to prove.

    Mr. SCOTT. You indicated that if you have a general application and you have a secular gathering, why not churches?

    Mr. MAUCK. Yes, Mr. Scott. The question generally gets asked, suppose you cannot have the gatherings, why should churches be special, particularly in light of the Justice Stevens' representation that this would be an establishment and should get thrown out summarily?
 Page 261       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Churches are entitled to at least two protections. They are entitled to be equally protected under the 14th Amendment, and they are entitled to the protection of the Free Exercise Clause of the First Amendment. So even if everybody was equally discriminated against, which I don't think could happen, for a city to say, we won't have any meeting halls or community centers at all, a community still must provide a zone where people may purchase a building to worship without having to get special permission. And that is not an establishment. The proposed law functions really to prevent an establishment. For an existing community to say that we are not going to allow any new churches unless we say so because we already have established churches would violate the Establishment Clause. What we are talking about is new churches that want to come in or expand, so we are balancing those two constitutional rights Free Exercise and No Establishment.

    Mr. SCOTT. This does not create a special privilege for churches that other people cannot enjoy? The statute provided the church with a legal weapon that no atheist or agnostic can obtain. The government preference for religion as opposed to irreligion is forbidden by the First Amendment. That is from Justice Stevens' concurring opinion. Is it your view that he can't get five votes to sustain that position?

    Mr. MAUCK. I wouldn't think so, but the—I would hate to guess. But religious land use rights are also protected under the Free Speech right, and the Court has recognized that land uses in the area of Free Speech, particularly adult uses, must be allowed in every community.

    We now have laws all over this country that say no church can come into our community unless we give you a permit. Those laws would be absolutely unconstitutional if they had to do with adult uses.
 Page 262       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    So pornographers now have more rights to come into our communities, because the Supreme Court has said you must have a zone where you can locate, than churches, and all we are asking is let's rectify the situation and give churches the same access that adult movie theaters have.

    Mr. SCOTT. Adult movie theaters are not governed by the time, place and manner restrictions? I mean, because it is an adult bookstore, it has rights that other similar gatherings wouldn't have?

    Mr. MAUCK. Because they are protected under the Free Speech Clause, the Supreme Court has said in land use regulation, you must allow an area where they can locate. That area is not defined. It has got to be a reasonable area. In some cases it has been found to be 5 percent of the community allows it. Am I answering your question?

    Mr. SCOTT. Well, I think you are answering it. I am not sure I agree with it.

    Mr. MAUCK. That is what the Court has said. But——

    Mr. SCOTT. Well, if they prohibit all gatherings, you are suggesting that there is a free speech exemption from a general application? I mean, if they say you can have stores but you can't have stores that say this content, then I can see how that could get thrown out.

 Page 263       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    Mr. MAUCK. Yes, but——

    Mr. SCOTT. I don't see how if—if you have no stores, period, I don't see how an adult bookstore would have super rights to come in and sell adult books.

    Mr. MAUCK. I believe the case is Schad v. Borough of Mount Ephraim.

    Mr. SCOTT. Could you repeat that again?

    Mr. MAUCK. Schad v. Borough of Mount Ephraim. It is a 1981 case—452 U.S. 61—has said you must have a zone where you allow adult uses. And they didn't—in that case, there was a small commercial area in the city. It wasn't a fact situation where there were no commercial areas at all.

    Mr. SCOTT. Could I have one additional minute, Mr. Chairman?

    Mr. CANADY. The gentleman can have two additional minutes.

    Mr. SCOTT. Thank you.

    Professor Durham, why aren't the civil rights laws sufficient to accomplish what we are trying to accomplish?

 Page 264       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    Mr. DURHAM. Well, I think one of the fundamental things, just viewed globally, is that we are dealing here with the relative priority of equality and liberty. And in general, while it is true that in our tradition we protect equality, it is vital to understand that tradition, there are cases where religious freedom, along with other sorts of freedom, takes priority.

    Part of the greatness of our tradition in religious liberty will be impoverished if we do not understand that at its core, it is about the protection of religious differences, religious pluralism and religious conscience. It is the pressure to try and transform——

    Mr. SCOTT. But you are—you are talking about minority religions. If you can build a church in an area, you ought not to be able to discriminate against a particular religion.

    Mr. DURHAM. Right.

    Mr. SCOTT. The civil rights laws, I think, are clearly competent to deal with that.

    The question is, if you don't allow any gatherings, no buildings, historic district, it is across the board, should those who are building a building for religious purposes be given additional rights, notwithstanding the Establishment Clause, that other people do not enjoy?

 Page 265       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    Mr. DURHAM. I would say yes.

    Mr. SCOTT. Didn't Boerne rule the other way? I mean, how could we do it if you are looking at a Supreme Court decision? I mean, I voted for the bill so obviously I agree with you.

    Mr. DURHAM. I think ultimately that one has to understand that the Establishment Clause and the Free Exercise Clause work together, and it is a perversion of First Amendment jurisprudence to think that the Establishment Clause in these contexts has so much force that it overrides free exercise.

    Mr. SCOTT. How do you—how do you fit that view into the Boerne decision, which, you know, I mean, you can agree or disagree with it, but it is there?

    Mr. DURHAM. I have to say that the Boerne decision is problematic, but distinguishable. I am not sure it is the Boerne decision so much as the Smith decision in the first place that is the problem. But in the meantime, going back to your question about why the discrimination statutes are not enough. The problem is they don't adequately take into account the range of religious freedom that is legitimate to take into account in this country.

    Mr. SCOTT. Thank you, Mr. Chairman.

    Mr. CANADY. Mr. Nadler.
 Page 266       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Mr. NADLER. Thank you.

    Mr. Durham or Professor Durham? Professor Durham, you said that minority religions representing less than 9 percent of the population involved over 49 percent of the cases regarding the right to locate religious buildings at a particular site.

    Mr. DURHAM. Right.

    Mr. NADLER. This is prima facie evidence that, in fact, there is discrimination going on, although perhaps not provable, correct; that is why you cite the figure?

    Mr. DURHAM. Right. The problem is that this is just the tip of the iceberg. What we don't see here are all the cases that never reach court.

    Mr. NADLER. Yes, but you are saying—but the basic proposition——

    Mr. DURHAM. Right.

    Mr. NADLER [continuing]. That this illustrates—I assume that what you are saying is that the basic proposition that this illustrates is that under the guise of neutral zoning laws, in fact, there is a lot of religious discrimination against minority religions going on?
 Page 267       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Mr. DURHAM. Right.

    Mr. NADLER. Okay. Now, the gentleman from Virginia asked why can't the antidiscrimination civil rights laws handle this. Am I correct in asserting or assuming that under the civil rights laws or the existing discrimination laws, in order to deal with this, you would have to prove discrimination in a particular case?

    Mr. DURHAM. I have to admit I am not an expert on the civil rights laws.

    Mr. NADLER. You would have to prove intentional discrimination, and I think you would have to prove it in a particular case, to show that here there is discrimination, that the reason this church is not getting its zoning is because they don't like this church or they don't want this church but some other church might have gotten it.

    Whereas the point of this law, or this proposed law, this bill, is that recognizing the kind of evidence of these statistics, we are going to say we know discrimination is going on and we are trying to use the general power of Congress to stop it without having to prove the specifics. I assume you would assume—you would agree that that is a real difference between this and the——

    Mr. DURHAM. Sure.

    Mr. NADLER. Do you have a study—can you get us the studies that show this? Not this moment, but do you have the studies?
 Page 268       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Mr. DURHAM. You mean the studies attached to the report that I am——

    Mr. NADLER. They are in the appendix here?

    Mr. DURHAM. Yes.

    Mr. NADLER. Then they are in the record.

    Thank you very much.

    Let me just say that in response to some of what has been said in the—I should mention also, before I go into what I was going to say, that in Boerne only Mr. Justice Stevens raised the Establishment Clause issue. Three justices argued that Smith should be reconsidered. The majority said nothing about the Establishment Clause issue, and I don't think Boerne can be read to say that the Establishment Clause issue in this case is in conflict—or in this situation is in conflict with the Free Exercise Clause.

    Do you agree with that?

    Mr. DURHAM. Yes. When we were preparing—well, when Mr. Laycock was preparing for argument, there was a sense that the establishment claim was not a really serious issue, that it would not really attract any significant following for the Court, and in fact, a lot of weight was not put on that argument.
 Page 269       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    The establishment issue did end up being mentioned by Justice Stevens, but, again, the main opinion poses no establishment bar to giving priority to religious liberty, as I said before.

    Mr. NADLER. Thank you. Let me comment on that, if I may, and on some of what Professor Hamilton—or the import of Professor Hamilton's comments and some others before, especially when—I was struck by Professor Hamilton's comment that it is a question of power and that it is a zero sum game. If you permit the church to add a wing, then they may be advantaged, but the people who don't like the church to add a wing because it is against, I don't know, zoning density or whatever, it is against their interests, and that it is a zero sum game, and it is always a religious interest versus some other interest, and we shouldn't be favoring the religious interest. And I think that is a fair summary of what was said and what was implied by some others.

    I just want to say that I think there is a fundamental difference. And I don't know if it is a constitutional difference, but it is a fundamental value difference, and I believe it is the heart of the purpose of the Bill of Rights and certainly the First Amendment, and that is freedom of conscience.

    There is a difference between someone's—there is a—this country, except when absolutely unavoidable, should not permit government, whether State, local or Federal, to put someone in a position of violating his conscience, especially his religious conscience, or obeying the law. And the girl in the gym class is one example. The person—I can think of other examples.
 Page 270       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    If some local school district decided to hold classes on Saturday and Orthodox Jews couldn't go to school on Saturday, you can imagine a million different example.

    Mr. CANADY. The gentleman will have three additional minutes.

    Mr. NADLER. Thank you. We should not, and I think it is a core value that people's freedom of religious conscience should, to the extent possible—and that is why I think the strict scrutiny test is a good test—to the extent possible, without invading other people's liberties, should be respected; that people should not be put in the position of violating their conscience. And there is a difference between someone's desire to have less traffic in a neighborhood, which is a legitimate desire, and someone's absolutely existential problem of violating either the law or their religious conscience, and that in a society that values religious freedom has to have a higher value. And that is, I think, what we are trying to do here.

    Mr. DURHAM. Well, that is certainly, I think, what I was trying to articulate by referring to the priority of liberty.

    I think that the land use cases are simply one set of cases that is a broader problem, and I think what Mr. Laycock said earlier, that what you really have to recognize here is in a lot of cases, by getting people to come to the table and talk, they will find better solutions than would come about otherwise. But if the secular bureaucrat is told that what he is doing is a neutral general law, and that in any litigation or challenge he automatically wins, there is very little impetus to start that dialogue and to find a way out of the zero sum game.
 Page 271       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Mr. NADLER. I would agree with you as a practical matter, though I would go further and say that the question is not or should not be whether that bureaucrat—I don't like to use the word ''secular'' as opposed to ''religious''—the fact is the government official adjudicating some law or enforcing some law being insensitive to a religious or conscientious need, that religious free exercise right, number one, it could be accommodated hopefully by talking, but second of all, it should not be subject to the whim of a bureaucrat or to a majority vote unless it threatens the liberty of somebody else. That is the basic core principle.

    Mr. DURHAM. I think that is why Barnett was right and Scalia should have read it instead of Gobitis.

    Mr. NADLER. I yield back the balance of my time.

    Mr. CANADY. Thank you. I now recognize myself.

    I think it is important that the subcommittee look at the specific language of the provision that is in the bill we have under consideration. If we look—if we look at that specific language, one of the things——

    Mr. SCOTT. Mr. Chairman, do you have another copy of the bill? The copy I have was the draft, the 14th draft.

    Mr. CANADY. We can even provide you with a copy of it.
 Page 272       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Mr. SCOTT. It has been changed a little bit since then. Thank you.

    Mr. CANADY. This on pages 3 and 4. But one feature of the bill is that it takes into account the impact of decisions on the location of a church or other religious facility on neighboring properties or on the public health or safety. So, again, I emphasize here that this is not some absolute right for churches to come in or other religious institutions to come in and have their facilities put wherever they want them put. That clearly would not be the impact of this.

    The language most certainly requires a consideration of the impact that the location of the facilities would have on surrounding uses. And that is important. That is important for us to note here, and I believe as a matter of policy that is the way it should be.

    And none of us who are advocating this bill are suggesting that just because someone claims—makes a claim under the Free Exercise Clause, that that should trump all other considerations.

    Now, having said that, let me turn to Mr. Mauck and ask you this: Under the law as it is now, what kind of track record do you see in religious organizations? We have some statistics on this, but I am interested—and we have gotten that quantified here. But I would like to just get your anecdotal impression about how easy it is for minority religions to prevail when they are subjected to exclusion in the land use process.

 Page 273       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    Mr. MAUCK. I think there are two practical problems. A real serious one is getting State court judges to understand the constitutional issues. In my experience, they want to. They don't have enough litigation before them involving constitutional issues, and when they get a constitutional issue they don't quite know what to do with it. And then if I start talking with them about Church of the Lukumi Babalu, and they look at it and they see this is about Santeria sacrifices, they think it has nothing to do with a land use case. And the same with peyote-smoking drug counselors as in the Smith case, they are not seen as relevant to a zoning case.

    And I think what this committee can do and what Congress can do is take what is being said by the Supreme Court and put it into a law that is easy to read and easy to enforce and for judges to look at and attorneys to look at and say, here is something that is real practical.

    I don't see the land use sections of this law as being an end run around Boerne. I see it as taking the other Supreme Court precedents and setting them out in more clear generalities to help at the local level the attorney who is representing the minority church, who doesn't have the constitutional issues all the time, or the judge. So that is part one of my answer.

    The second problem, and I think it could be addressed with a little clarification in the law, is that some courts, including some Federal appellate courts, do not see land use as part of religious exercise. They see that as simply a secular activity that everybody engages in and should not be part of religious exercise. But the Supreme Court, and Justice Scalia, has said part of free exercise is assembling together, but that is just dicta at this point. But I think that would clearly be upheld, and it ought to be—I think it ought to be added. And then with those two—well, with that change, and also may I suggest another change?
 Page 274       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Mr. CANADY. Sure.

    Mr. MAUCK. In section 1(B)—B(1)(b) under land use regulation——

    Mr. CANADY. I will give myself three additional minutes. What page are you on?

    Mr. MAUCK. Page 4, line 6.

    It talks about denying the—or denies religious assemblies a reasonable location in the jurisdiction.

    I think the intent there is to have an area where religious groups can freely locate without discretionary governmental approval, and that could be better said by adding, ''location in the jurisdiction where it can freely locate without discretionary governmental approval;'' because some municipalities think that everything they do is reasonable and all of their special use standards are reasonable.

    The problem is that the local ordinances are so discretionary that they allow, in many cases, unconstitutional factors, such as prejudice, to invade the process.

    Mr. CANADY. So if I understand what you are saying, you would—that would end up requiring that there be a church zone or a religious facilities zone?
 Page 275       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Mr. MAUCK. No. What I am saying, most communities have a residential zone with subcategories, a commercial or business and a manufacturing or an industrial. Within those zones they have a multitude of freely permitted uses. A commercial use may have funeral parlors and theaters and restaurants, and if they allow churches in that area, fine. In other—in other communities, churches are allowed freely in the residential area, and they have to get a permit in the commercial area. That is fine as long as there is at least one substantial zone where——

    Mr. CANADY. As of right they would be——

    Mr. MAUCK. Where they can go as of right, without having to get a special use permit.

    Mr. NADLER. Would the chairman yield a moment?

    Mr. CANADY. I would be happy to yield.

    Mr. NADLER. Thank you.

    I have one question, Mr. Mauck. You know, what would you do about the situation, what you were just saying, that it is okay as long as there would be some specific location in the town for churches? Orthodox Jews have to walk to synagogue, and that is why in communities you may have small storefront synagogues or even assemblies in people's homes because people have to walk. So the fact that downtown a mile or two away or three, there is a place, a church or synagogue, that wouldn't help this. So how would what you are suggesting relate to this problem?
 Page 276       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Mr. MAUCK. Paragraph B wouldn't help in that situation. Either paragraph C, which gives religious assemblies equal standing, or paragraph A.

    Mr. CANADY. It seems to me that probably the solution to that problem would be found in paragraph A or subparagraph A, rather than the other provisions.

    Mr. MAUCK. And that is a real problem, by the way. There was a synagogue that met in a home in Miami, and they were—they have been shut out several times trying to just be allowed to worship, 15 or 20 people worship in a home.

    Mr. NADLER. You think this language would take care of that problem in A or B?

    Mr. MAUCK. I think A would, and B or C might, depending upon the particular local ordinance.

    Mr. NADLER. Thank you. I just want to make sure the record is clear on that point, that one of the purposes or intended effects of subparagraph A is for exactly that purpose.

    Mr. CANADY. Well, I appreciate the gentleman mentioning that. As the gentleman may recall at a press conference where we spoke about this bill on the day of its introduction, that is a particular example that I used of one of the most egregious abuses of religious liberty, and it is important that we do what we can here to correct that specific problem.
 Page 277       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Mr. NADLER. Thank you, Mr. Chairman.

    Mr. CANADY. Mr. Scott, Mr. Nadler, if you have additional questions.

    Mr. NADLER. I don't.

    Mr. SCOTT. Mr. Chairman, I would ask——

    Mr. CANADY. Mr. Scott is recognized.

    Mr. SCOTT. Thank you. I would just ask that we ask the Department of Justice to express their opinion as to the constitutionality of the bill. They will be the ones that will have to defend it if and when it goes to the Supreme Court, and we would like them to have an opportunity to be heard.

    Mr. CANADY. I think that that is a good idea.

    Mr. SCOTT. I yield back.

    Mr. CANADY. With that, this hearing will come to a conclusion.

    I want to thank the members of our second panel. Your testimony has been very helpful in focusing on the specific issue where the bill acts pursuant to Congress' authority under section 5.
 Page 278       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Mr. SCOTT. Could I ask another question?

    Mr. CANADY. The gentleman from Virginia is recognized.

    Mr. SCOTT. There is one kind of technical question on the land use. Page 4, line 17, it says, section 2 does not apply. Section 2 includes the Commerce Clause and the Spending Clause. So is it the reading of the witnesses that we are relegated to section 5 enforcement?

    Mr. MAUCK. I think the Land Use sections of the Religious Liberty Protection Act is a valid exercise of Congress' power under at least two constitutional provisions. First, the Enforcement Clause of the 14th Amendment gives the Congress power to enact laws where, according to the Flores case. Congress has evidence of systematic violation of constitutional rights. I have given you evidence of widespread religious, ethnic, racial and socio-economic discrimination in the sphere of zoning and will supplement the record in that regard. The second basis for Congressional enactment authority is the Commerce Clause. The Commerce Clause does not authorize religious regulation but does authorize Congress to restrain local governments in their over regulation o fuses affecting commerce. Other witnesses have shown the massive effect of church construction, church relocation and other religious land use on commerce. If Congress discerns that local land use regulations are negatively affecting commerce by, for example, the race to erect ever higher barriers to land use between municipalities or states then they can and should retrain those abuses as an exercise in prudent Federalism. Municipalities cannot end the higher barriers ''arms race'' themselves and states, to a large extent, are also powerless. Congress is uniquely positioned to ''demilitarize'' the zoning codes under the Commerce Clause.
 Page 279       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Well, I don't think it should be, if that is what it is saying, that this is not a commerce issue, because it does—at least as I see it, in every zoning hearing, every zoning board says this is a commerce issue. That is how the local communities see it: We want more business and less church.

    Mr. CANADY. With the indulgence of the members of the subcommittee, I think it would be appropriate and helpful to have Professor Laycock, if he would be willing to address that specific point, because in the statement he has provided the committee, he has addressed that.

    Mr. LAYCOCK. Thank you, Mr. Chairman. It is in the statement. My understanding of the intention of that provision is to say that the compelling interest test in section 2 does not apply to land use, so that the land use authorities do not face a double hurdle of first they have to show that they have complied with A, B and C, and then in addition they have to show that they meet the compelling interest test. The substantive standard is one or the other.

    But I think the committee should make clear that that provision does not say anything about what sources of constitutional authority Congress is relying on to enact the land use provisions. Those provisions are primarily intended as acts to enforce the Fourteenth Amendment, but in many of their applications, they will also be cases affecting commerce, and Congress can rely on the Commerce Clause—certainly in construction cases and probably in lots of other cases. And there may even be occasional cases where there is some sort of Federal aid and there is a Spending Clause application.

 Page 280       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  
    Mr. SCOTT. Let me ask it another way. Line 18, which is in section 2, are you really aiming at just such sections 2 (B), (C), (D) and (E), and not section 2(A)?

    Mr. LAYCOCK. My copy of the bill doesn't have numbered lines. I had to get it off the Internet.

    Mr. SCOTT. Section 2 says, general rule, and 2(A)(1) says, Federal assistance.

    Mr. CANADY. If I could just interject here. I think that there would be a conflict because the standard set forth in section 2 is a different standard than that set forth in section 4, the section on land use that we are focusing on; section 3(B).

    Mr. LAYCOCK. I think we have to think——

    Mr. CANADY. It is a more particularized standard that relates to land use than the general standard articulated in the earlier section.

    Mr. LAYCOCK. That is right. We clearly don't want the compelling interest test to apply. This language has been tinkered with since the last time I saw it, and we may have to think through it very carefully and make sure we have got it right. And, Mr. Scott, it may only be some subsections that do not apply.

    Mr. SCOTT. Is it your intention that the relevance of the Commerce Clause and Federal assistance would apply to section 3?
 Page 281       PREV PAGE       TOP OF DOC    Segment 1 Of 2  

    Mr. LAYCOCK. Yes. That was clearly the intention of the coalition when they began talking to the Members about the bill.

    Mr. SCOTT. Thank you, Mr. Chairman.

    Mr. CANADY. Again, I want to thank you for participating in our hearing today. Your testimony is very valuable to the considerations of the subcommittee. The subcommittee stands adjourned.

    [Whereupon, at 1:10 p.m., the subcommittee was adjourned.]

Next Hearing Segment(2)









(Footnote 1 return)
Cf. Salinas v. United States, 118 S.Ct. 469, 475 (1997). Salinas interpreted 18 U.S.C. §666(a)(1)(B) (1994), part of the federal bribery statute, to apply to any bribe accepted in a covered federally assisted program, whether or not the federal funds were in any way affected. The Court also concluded that under that interpretation, ''there is no serious doubt about the constitutionality of §666(a)(1)(B) as applied to the facts of this case.'' Preferential treatment accorded to one federal prisoner (the briber) ''was a threat to the integrity and proper operation of the federal program,'' even if it cost nothing and diverted no federal funds. The Court did not find it necessary to consider whether there might someday be an application in which the statute would be unconstitutional as applied.


(Footnote 2 return)
See the Clayton Act, 15 U.S.C. §18 (1994) (''person engaged in commerce or in any activity affecting commerce''); the Federal Trade Commission Act, 15 U.S.C. §45 (1994) (''unfair or deceptive acts or practices in or affecting commerce''); the Federal Fire Prevention and Control Act, 15 U.S.C. §2224 (1994) (''places of public accommodation affecting commerce''); the Petroleum Marketing Practices Act, 15 U.S.C. §2801 (1994) (trade, etc., ''which affects any trade, transportation, exchange, or other commerce'' between any state and any place outside of such state); the Semiconductor Chip Protection Act, 17 U.S.C. §910 (1994) (''conduct in or affecting commerce''); the criminal provisions of the Health Insurance Portability and Accountability Act, 18 U.S.C. §24 (Supp. II 1996) (''any public or private plan or contract, affecting commerce''); the Federally Protected Activities Act, 18 U.S.C. §245 (1994) (''engaged in a business in commerce or affecting commerce''); the National Labor Relations Act, 29 U.S.C. §152 (1994) (''affecting commerce''); the Labor-Management Reporting and Disclosure Act, 29 U.S.C. §402 (1994) (''industry affecting commerce''); the Age Discrimination in Employment Act, 29 U.S.C. §630 (1994) (''industry affecting commerce''); the Occupational Safety and Health Act (OSHA), 29 U.S.C. §652 (1994) (''engaged in a business affecting commerce''); the Employment and Retirement Income Security Act (ERISA), 29 U.S.C. §1003 (1994) (''in commerce or in any industry or activity affecting commerce''); the Employee Polygraph Protection Act, 29 U.S.C. §2002 (1994) (''any employer engaged in or affecting commerce''); the Family and Medical Leave Act, 29 U.S.C. §2611 (1994) (''industry or activity affecting commerce''); Title II of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, 42 U.S.C. §2000a (1994) (''if its operations affect commerce''); Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, 42 U.S.C. §2000e (''engaged in an industry affecting commerce''); the Privacy Protection Act, 42 U.S.C. §2000aa (Supp. II 1996) (''public communication, in or affecting interstate or foreign commerce''); the Energy Policy and Conservation Act, 42 U.S.C. §6291 (1994) (trade, etc., ''which affects any trade, transportation, exchange, or other commerce'' between any state and any place outside of such state); the Americans with Disabilities Act, 42 U.S.C. §12111 (1994) (''engaged in an industry affecting commerce''); the Commercial Motor Vehicle Safety Act, 42 U.S.C. §31101 (1994) (''engaged in a business affecting commerce'').


(Footnote 3 return)
See, e.g., Capitol Square Review & Advisory Board v. Pinette, 515 U.S. 753 (1995); Rosenberger v. Rector of the Univ. of Va., 515 U.S. 819 (1995); Lamb's Chapel v. Center Moriches Union Free School Dist., 508 U.S. 384 (1993); Widmar v. Vincent, 454 U.S. 263 (1981); Metromedia, Inc. v. City of San Diego, 453 U.S. 490 (1984); Carey v. Brown, 447 U.S. 455 (1980); Police Dept. v. Mosley, 408 U.S. 92 (1972).


(Footnote 4 return)
Tyler v. Murphy, 135 F.3d 594 (8th Cir. 1998); Hadix v. Johnson, 133 F.3d 940 (6th Cir. 1998), cert. petition filed (Apr. 13, 1998, No. 97–1693); Dougan v. Singletary, 129 F.3d 1424 (11th Cir. 1997), cert. petition filed (Mar. 2, 1998, No. 97–8120); Inmates of Suffolk County Jail v. Rouse, 129 F.3d 649, 657–58 (1st Cir. 1997), cert. petition filed, 66 U.S.L.W. 3531 (Feb. 4, 1998, No. 97–1278); Benjamin v. Johnson, 124 F.3d 162 (2d Cir. 1997); Gavin v. Branstad, 122 F.3d 1081 (8th Cir. 1997), cert. petition filed (Jan. 5, 1998, No. 97–7420); Plyler v. Moore, 100 F.3d 365 (4th Cir. 1996), cert. denied, 117 S.Ct. 2460 (1997); but cf. Taylor v. United States, 1998 Westlaw 214578 (9th Cir., May 4, 1998).


(Footnote 5 return)
This conclusion probably does not include the Spending Clause. The Court noted ''the unremarkable, and completely unrelated, proposition that the States may waive their sovereign immunity.'' Id. at 65. Congress may be able to require that states waive their Eleventh Amendment immunity with respect to programs for which they voluntarily accept federal financial assistance. Immunity would then be removed not by legislation under Article I, but by the consent of the state. But RLPA does not embody this theory; the override of immunity does not include claims under the Spending Clause provisions.


(Footnote 6 return)
Sasnett v. Sullivan, 908 F. Supp. 1429, 1440–47 (W.D. Wis. 1995), aff'd, 91 F.3d 1018, 1022 (7th Cir. 1996), vacated on other grounds, 117 S.C. 2502 (1997); Muslim v. Frame, 891 F. Supp. 226, 229–31 (E.D. Pa. 1995), rehearing denied, 897 F. Supp. 216, 217–20 (E.D. Pa. 1995), aff'd mem., possibly on other grounds, 107 F.3d 7 (3d Cir. 1997); Mack v. O'Leary, 80 F.3d 1175, 1178–80 (7th Cir. 1996), vacated on other grounds, 118 S.Ct. 36 (1997).


(Footnote 7 return)
City of Boerne v. Flores, 117 S.Ct. 2157, 2173 (Scalia, J., concurring) (''religiously motivated conduct''); id. at 2174 (same); id. at 2177 (O'Connor, J., concurring) (same); id. at 2178 (same); Church of the Lukumi Babalu Aye, Inc. v. City of Hialeah, 508 U.S. 520, 524 (''conduct motivated by religious beliefs''); id. at 533 (''religious motivation''); id. at 538 (same); id. at 543 (''conduct with religious motivation''); id. at 545 (''conduct motivated by religious belief''); id. at 546 (''conduct with a religious motivation''); id. at 547 (''conduct motivated by religious conviction''); id. at 560 n.1 (Souter, J., concurring) (''conduct motivated by religious belief''); id. at 563 (''religiously motivated conduct''); id. (''conduct . . . undertaken for religious reasons'') (quoting Employment Div. v. Smith, 494 U.S. at 532); id. at 578 (Blackmun, J., concurring) (''religiously motivated practice'').


(Footnote 8 return)
James Madison, Memorial and Remonstrance Against Religious Assessments, para. 1.


(Footnote 9 return)
494 U.S. 872 (1990).


(Footnote 10 return)
117 S. Ct. 2157 (1997).


(Footnote 11 return)
Brief Amicus Curiae of the Coalition for the Free Exercise of Religion, City of Boerne v. Flores (No. 95–2074), at 11.


(Footnote 12 return)
It was only about two a half years between the time the statute was enacted and the time RFRA litigation went largely on hold as a result of the pendency of the Boerne case in the Supreme Court.


(Footnote 13 return)
Mocklaitis v. Harcleroad, 104 F.3d 1522 (9th Cir. 1997).


(Footnote 14 return)
Stuart Circle Parish v. Bd. of Zoning Appeals, 946 F. Supp. 1225 (E.D. Va. 1996); Western Presbyterian Church v. Bd. of Zoning Adjustment, 862 F. Supp. 538 (D.D.C. 1994); Jesus Center v. Farmington Hills Zoning Bd. of Appeals, 544 N.W.2d 698 Mich. App. 1996).


(Footnote 15 return)
See, e.g., State v. Miller, 196 Wis. 2d 238, 538 N.W.2d 573 (Wis. App. 1995) (Amish drivers di not have to display bright orange emblems); Cheema v. Thompson, 67 F.3d 883 (9th Cir. 1995) (Sikh students permitted to wear sewn-up ceremonial knives); Sasnett v. Sullivan, 91 F.3d 1018 (7th Cir. 1996), vacated on grounds of Boerne, 117 S. Ct. 2502 (1997) (prisoners permitted to wear crucifixes as against ban on religious jewelry).


(Footnote 16 return)
Memorandum from Michael Farris and Bradley Jacob, HSLDA, at 2 (''HSLDA Mem.''). See also id. at 10 (advocating that Congress should not ''acquiesce[] in the atrocious Boerne decision'').


(Footnote 17 return)
U.S. Const., art. I, sec. 8, cl. 1.


(Footnote 18 return)
Title VI, Civil Rights Act of 1964, 42 U.S.C. 2000d (race); Title IX, Education Amendments of 1972, 20 U.S.C. 1681 (sex); Rehabilitation Act of 1973, 29 U.S.C. 794 (handicap); Age Discrimination in Employment Act of 1975, Title III, 42 U.S.C. 6102 (age).


(Footnote 19 return)
See, e.g., Mozert v. Hawkins County Bd. of Educ., 827 F.2d 1058 (6th Cir. 1987) (textbook series); Brown v. Hot, Sexy, and Safer Productions, 68 F.3d 525 (1st Cir. 1995) (explicit sex education program); Curtis v. School Committee of Falmouth, 420 Mass. 749, 652 N.E.2d 280 (1995) (distribution of condoms without notice to parents).


(Footnote 20 return)
483 U.S. 203 (1987).


(Footnote 21 return)
Current law strongly supports the Spending Power standard; but if Congress is concerned that the Court will begin to impose federalism limitations on that power, it might do some incremental tightening to the definition of a covered ''program or activity.'' The goal would be to prevent the provision of funds to one small part of a large state-wide agency, like the transportation or human services department, from justifying conditions on wholly unrelated parts of that agency.


(Footnote 22 return)
HSLDA Mem. at 4.


(Footnote 23 return)
Hsu v. Roslyn Union Free School Dist. No. 3, 85 F.2d 839 (2d Cir. 1996) (indicating that Equal Access Act, 20 U.S.C. 4071 et seq., does not resolve all such questions).


(Footnote 24 return)
See Cheema, 67 F.3d 883; see also Chalifoux v. New Caney Indpdt. School. Dist., 976 F. Supp. 659 (S.D. Tex. 1997) (protecting students' rights to wear rosaries, based on First Amendment rationale).


(Footnote 25 return)
See, e.g., Vandiver v. Hardin County Bd. of Educ., 925 F.2d 927 (6th Cir. 1991) (upholding school's discretion under Smith and rejecting ''hybrid'' claim).


(Footnote 26 return)
HSLDA Mem. at 9 (arguing that ''reduction of faith and religious practice to commerce'' is ''sacrilegious'' and ''at the very least silly''); Letter to Members of Congress from Michael Farris et al. (describing Commerce Power rationale as ''an affront to our faith'' because ''[w]orship is not commerce'' (emphasis in original)).


(Footnote 27 return)
Letter from Farris et al., supra.


(Footnote 28 return)
HSLDA Mem at 6, 10.


(Footnote 29 return)
Civil Rights Cases, 109 U.S. 3 (1883).


(Footnote 30 return)
See Gerald Gunther, Constitutional Law 151 n.5 (12th ed. 1991) (quoting Sen. Cooper).


(Footnote 31 return)
Id. at 150–51 (quoting Sen. Pastore).


(Footnote 32 return)
See, e.g., Burton v. Wilmington Parking Authority, 365 U.S. 715 (1961) (privately-owned restaurant that leased space in a municipal parking garage was a state actor and so could refuse to serve blacks). Thus, constitutional expert Gerald Gunther urged that the federal government could profitably ''channel its resources of ingenuity and advocacy into the development of a viable interpretation of the Fourteenth Amendment, the provision with a natural linkage to the race problem.'' See Gunther, supra, at 149 (quoting letter to Justice Department, June 5, 1963).


(Footnote 33 return)
In section 5, ''Rules of Construction.''


(Footnote 34 return)
514 U.S. 549, 115 S. Ct. 1624 (1995)


(Footnote 35 return)
115 S. Ct. at 1631.


(Footnote 36 return)
While other witnesses can provide more detailed statistics, I will cite just one indicator. According to a leading survey, charitable contributions to religious entities nationwide in 1996 totaled $69.44 billion (a figure that appears even to leave out some contributions to religiously affiliated universities). American Association of Fund-Raising Counsel, Giving USA 1997 (summary available at http://www.aafrc.org). Since religious organizations also receive revenue from investments, quid-pro-quo transactions, and direct or indirect government funding, it is easy to see that their yearly receipts—and thus presumably their expenditures—exceed $100 billion.


(Footnote 37 return)
115 S. Ct. at 1630 (reaffirming the ''aggregation'' theory of Wickard v. Filburn, 317 U.S. 111 (1942)).


(Footnote 38 return)
Just a few of many examples include United States v. Robinson, 119 F.3d 1205, 1214–15 (5th Cir. 1997) (upholding federal law against extortion); United States v. Chowdbury, 118 F.3d 742, 745 (11th Cir. 1997) (upholding federal law against arson); United States v. Sodema, 82 F.3d 1370, 1373–74 (7th Cir. 1996) (upholding federal law against blocking access to clinics); United States v. Wilson, 73 F.3d 675, 685 (7th Cir. 1995) (same).


(Footnote 39 return)
HSLDA Mem. at 5.


(Footnote 40 return)
See, e.g., McClure v. Salvation Army, 460 F.2d 553 (5th Cir. 1972) (Salvation Army was within commerce and covered by Title VII, although its ministerial relations were exempt because of First Amendment concerns); Volunteers of America v. NLRB, 777 F.2d 1386, 1388 (9th Cir. 1985) (church-operated alcohol rehabilitation center affected commerce and was subject to National Labor Relations Act); NLRB v. Salvation Army Day Care Center, 763 F.2d 1, 6 (1st Cir. 1985) (same, for religious day care center); VOA-Minnesota-Bar None Boys Ranch v. NLRB, 752 F.2d 345, 349 (8th Cir,. 1985) (same, for religious residential children's home for children); St. Elizabeth Hospital v. NLRB, 715 F,2d 1193, 1196 (7th Cir. 1983) (same, for religious hospital); Dole v. Shenandoah Baptist Church, 707 F. Supp. 1450 (W.D. Va. 1989), aff'd, 899 F.2d 1389 (4th Cir. 1990) (church schools are within commerce under Fair Labor Standards Act); Dole v. Rose City Pentecostal Church of God, 1990 WL 127718 (E.D. Ark. 1990) (same).


(Footnote 41 return)
See, e.g., McClure, 460 F.2d 553 (exempting ministerial relationship from Title VII even though Salavation Army was within commerce); NLRB v. Catholic Bishop, 440 U.S. 490 (1979) (exempting church-operated schools from NLRA)..


(Footnote 42 return)
See, e.g., Title VII, sec. 702, 42 U.S.C. 2000e-1 (exempting religious organizations from liability for hiring members of their own faith, but assuming that they affect commerce); 29 C.F.R. 103.1 (NLRB policy to refrain from jurisdiction over any private school with less than $1 million annual revenues, not just over religious ones); Catholic Bishop, 440 U.S. at 497 (noting Board's policy of setting jurisdictional limit based on revenues).


(Footnote 43 return)
HSLDA Mem. at 6.


(Footnote 44 return)
See, e.g., Smith v. Fair Employment and Housing Comm., 12 Cal. 4th 1143, 51 Cal. Rptr. 2d 700, 913 P.2d 909 (Cal. 1996); Attorney General v. Desilets, 418 Mass. 316, 636 N.E.2d 233 (Mass. 1994).


(Footnote 45 return)
United States v. Printz, 117 S. Ct. 2365, 2380 (1997); accord New York v. United States, 505 U.S. 144 (1992).


(Footnote 46 return)
See Daniel O. Conkle, Congressional Alternatives in the Wake of City of Boerne v. Flores: The (Limited) Role of Congress in Protecting Religious Freedom from State and Local Infringement, 20 U. Ark. Little Rock L. J.XX(forthcoming 1998) (also making a similar argument based on Lopez).


(Footnote 47 return)
RLPA section 2(d).


(Footnote 48 return)
Menora v. Illinois High School Assn., 683 F.2d 1030, 1035–36 (7th Cir. 1982).


(Footnote 49 return)
New York, 505 U.S. at 166.


(Footnote 50 return)
Airline Deregulation Act of 1978, 47 U.S.C. 41701.


(Footnote 51 return)
Staggers Rail Act of 1980, 40 U.S.C. 10505. The Act's provision authorizing the Interstate Commerce Commission to exempt carriers from certain regulation, 40 U.S.C. 10505(a), has often been interpreted to preempt state regulations. G&T Terminal Packaging Co. V. Consolidated Rail Corp., 830 F.2d 1230, 1233–36 (3d Cir. 1987); Alliance Shippers Inc. v. Southern Pacific Transp. Co., 858 F.2d 567 (9th Cir. 1988) (per curiam).


(Footnote 52 return)
Morales v. Trans World Airlines, 504 U.S. 374, 378 (1992) (interpreting and applying 47 U.S.C. 41713(b)).


(Footnote 53 return)
483 U.S. 327 (1987).


(Footnote 54 return)
Id. at 334, 336.


(Footnote 55 return)
Id. at 338.


(Footnote 56 return)
See Gillette v. United States, 401 U.S. 437 (1971) (upholding draft exemption for religious conscientious objectors); Selective Draft Law Cases, 245 U.S. 366 (1918); see also Board of Education, Kiryas Joel School Dist. v. Grumet, 512 U.S. 587, 114 S. Ct. 2481, 2492–93 (1994); Employment Division v. Smith, 494 U.S. 872, 890 (1990); Hobbie v. Unemployment Appeals Comm., 480 U.S. 136, 144–45 (1987) (all stating that legislatures may exempt religious conduct).


(Footnote 57 return)
See United States v. Salerno, 481 U.S. 739, 745 (1987) (a statute should be upheld on its face unless ''no set of circumstances exists under which [it] would be valid'').


(Footnote 58 return)
Christians v. Crystal Evangelical Free Church, 1998 WL 166642 (8th Cir. April 13, 1998).


(Footnote 59 return)
See Marci A. Hamilton, The Religious Freedom Restoration Act: Letting the Fox into the Henhouse under Cover of Section 5 of the Fourteenth Amendment, 16 Cardozo L. Rev. 357 (1994); Eugene Gressman and Angela C. Carmella, The RFRA Revision of the Free Exercise Clause, 57 Ohio St. L. J. 65 (1996).


(Footnote 60 return)
Bob Jones University v. United States, 461 U.S. 574 (1983).


(Footnote 61 return)
Id. at 604.


(Footnote 62 return)
See id. at 604 n.29.


(Footnote 63 return)
See, e.g., Smith v. Fair Employment and Housing Comm., 12 Cal. 4th 1143, 51 Cal. Rptr. 2d 700, 913 P.2d 909, 928–29 (Cal. 1996) (plurality opinion).


(Footnote 64 return)
Flores clearly invalidated RFRA with respect to the regulation of state and local government behavior. Courts have divided about whether Flores should be understood to invalidate RFRA with regard to regulation of federal behavior. Yet, regardless of whether RFRA's federal applications survived Flores, we expect that the federal courts should, and will, ultimately declare them to be unconstitutional. For reasons that are equally applicable to RLPA and so are discussed in this memorandum, we believe that RFRA is unconstitutional under the Supreme Court's Establishment Clause doctrine.


(Footnote 65 return)
See, e.g., Mack v. O'Leary, 80 F.3d 1175, 1179 (7th Cir. 1996) (''a substantial burden on the free exercise of religion . . . is one that forces adherents of a religion to refrain from religiously motivated conduct, inhibits or constrains conduct or expression that maintains a central tenet of a person's religious belief, or compels conduct or expression that is contrary to those beliefs''); Bryant v. Gomez, 46 F. 3d 948, 949 (9th Cir. 1995) (to meet the substantial burden standard, plaintiffs must point to a burden that is '' 'more than an inconvenience; the burden must be substantial and an interference with a tenet or belief that is central to religious doctrine.' '' (quoting Graham v. C.I.R., 822 F.2d 844, 850–51 (9th Cir. 1987), aff'd sub nom. Hernandez v. Commissioner, 490 U.S. 680 (1988)); Thiry v. Carlson, 78 F.3d 1491, 1495 (10th Cir. 1996) (''To exceed the 'substantial burden' threshold, government regulation 'must significantly inhibit or constrain conduct or expression that manifests some central tenet of . . . [an individual's] beliefs; must meaningfully curtail [an individual's] ability to express adherence to his or her faith; or must deny [an individual] reasonable opportunities to engage in those activities that are fundamental to [an individual's] religion''' (quoting Werner v. McCotter, 49 F. 3d 1476, 1480 (10th Cir. 1995) (brackets and ellisions added by the Thiry Court)); Cheffer v. Reno, 55 F.3d 1517, 1522 (11th Cir. 1995) (no substantial burden results if a government action ''leaves ample avenues open for plaintiffs to express their deeply held belief[s]'').


(Footnote 66 return)
RLPA's use of the Spending Power may also raise additional Establishment Clause problems beyond those discussed above. RLPA in effect uses every federal spending program as a device to favor religion. The use of spending programs to favor religion (and only religion) has always been regarded as a paradigmatic example of an Establishment Clause violation. We believe that Section 2(a)(1) of RLPA would be clearly unconstitutional on this ground alone. This point is in fact related to the absence of any nexus between RLPA and the purposes of particular government spending programs. Were there such a nexus, it might be difficult to say that RLPA was designed only to benefit religion: it could be regarded as incidental to the goals of some particular program (say, an anti-discrimination program or a cultural affairs program) which bore a plausible relationship to some forms of religious conduct. Absent that nexus, however, RLPA is nothing more than a naked effort to use government spending to improve the position of religious persons and institutions.


(Footnote 67 return)
Professor Douglas Laycock tilts at windmills when he attempts to argue that the test instituted by RLPA (and RFRA), the compelling interest/least restrictive means test, was the test regularly employed in all free exercise cases before 1990. He neglects to mention Turner v. Safley, 482 U.S. 78 (1987), which makes explicit that strict scrutiny does not apply in the prison context or any of other cases in which the Court demonstrated great deference to government interests. See, e.g., Goldman v. Weinberger, 475 U.S. 503 (1986); Bowen v. Roy, 476 U.S. 693 (1986). Whatever Professor Laycock's interpretation of the Supreme Court's free exercise jurisprudence may be, the Supreme Court itself made absolutely clear in Boerne v. Flores that the least restrictive means test is ''a requirement that was not used in the pre-Smith jurisprudence RFRA purported to codify.'' 117 S. Ct. at 2171.


(Footnote 68 return)
One of the empirical questions left to be answered in the wake of Smith is the actual incidence of truly neutral, generally applicable,laws. Having listened to a number of very smart lawyers for various religions, I am now persuaded that the burden of proving a law is not neutral may not be particularly heavy. We do not know how this issue will be determined in the courts yet, because RFRA made the Court's doctrine superfluous from 1993 until 1997, and Smith only became the law in 1990.


(Footnote 69 return)
City of Boerne v. Flores, 117 S.Ct. 2157, 2162–63 (1997).


(Footnote 70 return)
Flores, 117 S.Ct. at 2164, 2170.


(Footnote 71 return)
Seminole Tribe of Florida v. Florida, 517 U.S. 44, 58 (1996).


(Footnote 72 return)
E.g. Civil Rights Act of 1964, §701 et seq., 706(k) as amended.


(Footnote 73 return)
See 42 U.S.C. §2000d et seq. (1994).


(Footnote 74 return)
483 U.S. 203 (1987)


(Footnote 75 return)
Moreover, as with all federal spending conditions, the recipients of federal money are free to decline payment for a particular program if they do not wish to comply with the requirements established by Congress for that program.


(Footnote 76 return)
E.g., Corporation of the Presiding Bishop v. Amos, 483 U.S. 327 (1987).


(Footnote 77 return)
1998 WL 166642 (8th Cir. 1998).


(Footnote 78 return)
117 S.Ct. at 2162–72.


(Footnote 79 return)
The argument that the Act violates the ''enumerated powers requirement'' is frivolous. Of the key operative provisions, Section 2(a)(1) is obviously based on Congress's commerce power under Article I, Sec. 8, cl. 3; Section 2(a)(2) is plainly based on the spending power under Article I, Sec. 8, cl. 1, & Sec. 9; and Section 3 is expressly based on Section 5 of the Fourteenth Amendment. And the fact that the Act does not identify a specific arena of commerce or spending is irrelevant. The Act's opponents have not cited a single decision suggesting that such a requirement applies.


(Footnote 80 return)
494 U.S. 872 (1990).


(Footnote 81 return)
494 U.S. at 890.


(Footnote 82 return)
117 S. Ct. at 2176.


(Footnote 83 return)
Rome v. United States, 446 U.S. 156, 174 (1980); South Carolina v. Katzenbach, 383 U.S. 301, 328 (1966).


(Footnote 84 return)
E.g., Joshua 24:15; The Book of Mormon, Another Testament of Jesus Christ, 2 Nephi 2:11–12, 26–27; The Pearl of Great Price, Moses 7:32.


(Footnote 85 return)
E.g.,The Book of Mormon, Another Testament of Jesus Christ, 2 Nephi 1:6–7; 10:10–12; Ether 2:12; Doctrine & Covenants of the Church of Jesus Christ of Latter-Day Saints 101:76–80.


(Footnote 86 return)
E.g., NCAA v. Tarkanian, 488 U.S. 179 (1988).


(Footnote 87 return)
See, e.g., June 4, 1998 memorandum from Steve McFarland of the Center for Law and Religious Freedom to Hon. Charles Canady at 6 (''McFarland Memorandum'') (attached) (citing this and other examples).


(Footnote 88 return)
From Belief to Commitment (1993), p. xi.


(Footnote 89 return)
Giving USA (1990), p. 101.


(Footnote 90 return)
J. &.S. Ronsvalle, How Generous Are We? Christian Century, June 3–10, 1998, pp. 579–80.


(Footnote 91 return)
Statewide Summary of Exemptions by Property Group and Exemption Code, 1995 Assessment Roles, pages B.85–959, Table B.4


(Footnote 92 return)
State of Wisconsin Summary of Tax Exemption Devises, Feb. 1997, p. 100, Table 1.


(Footnote 93 return)
1996 Profile of Catholic Health Care.


(Footnote 94 return)
Modern Healthcare Multi-Unit Providers Survey, May 20, 1996.


(Footnote 95 return)
M. Shick & J. Dauber, The Financing of Jewish Day Schools, (1995).


(Footnote 96 return)
ATS Fact Book (1997–98), pp. 27, 103.


(Footnote 97 return)
October, 1997 pp. 1, 45.


(Footnote 98 return)
That Congress has the power to regulate religion does not mean that it should do so lightly.


(Footnote 99 return)
Take the recent case of the truck driver who refused to do long distance runs with a female partner, who would sleep in the back of the truck cabin. As I understand the case, he did not claim that women should not be truck drivers, only that he should be assigned a different partner. I believe he lost even this claim.


(Footnote 100 return)
James Madison, Memorial and Remonstrance Against Religious Assessments, reprinted in The Mind of the Founder: Sources of the Political Thought of James Madison, Marvin Meyers, ed. (rev. ed. 1981). The Memorial and Remonstrance is also reprinted as an appendix to Everson v. Board of Education, 330 U.S. 1, 63 (1947).


(Footnote 101 return)
City of Boerne v. Flores, 117 S. Ct. 2157 (1997); Employment Division v. Smith, 494 U.S. 872 (1990).


(Footnote 102 return)
Quoted in Carl Holliday, Woman's Life in Colonial Days 40 (Boston: Cornhill Publishing Company, 1992).


(Footnote 103 return)
My summary of the Survey draws on a summary prepared by Professor Angela Carmella in a chapter entitled ''Land Use Regulation of Churches'' that will appear in The Structure of American Churches: An Inquiry into the Impact of Legal Structures on Religious Freedom, which is to be published under the auspices of the DePaul Center for Church/State Studies. (I am an Associate Editor of this volume.)


(Footnote 104 return)
Survey, MQ41.


(Footnote 105 return)
44% of the organizations surveyed indicated owning one or more educational facilities. Survey, MQ14.


(Footnote 106 return)
Of these, 54% provide recreation centers, and 80% have campgrounds. Survey, MQ58 D and G.


(Footnote 107 return)
10% of these have a television station; 24% have a radio station.


(Footnote 108 return)
Id.


(Footnote 109 return)
Survey, MQ10, MQ42.


(Footnote 110 return)
Nearly one-third reported owning clergy housing or other real estate.


(Footnote 111 return)
Survey, MQ30.


(Footnote 112 return)
Technically, all religions in the United States are ''minority religions'' in the sense that their members constitute less than 50% of the population. It turns out that those with 1.5% of the population or more tend to include ''mainline'' groups, and that the less popular groups all fall below the 1.5% line.


(Footnote 113 return)
Supplement to the Session Annual Statistical Report: End of Year 1997, Question 7–8.


(Footnote 114 return)
See Statement of Von G. Keetch, pp. 11–17.


(Footnote 115 return)
Id. at 298 (citing District Court opinion).


(Footnote 116 return)
Id. at 298–99.


(Footnote 117 return)
Orthodox Minyan of Elkins Park v. Cheltenham Township Zoning Hearing Bd., 552 A.2d 772, 773 (Pa. Cmwlth. 1989)(''It is ironic that the Board denied a special exception to convert a property to religious use on the grounds of increasd traffic flow to a group whose religion prohibits them from driving automobiles during their day of worship'').


(Footnote 118 return)
310 U.S. 296, 304–307 (1940).


(Footnote 119 return)
508 U.S. 520, 534 (1993)(quoting Walz v. Tax Comm'n, 397 U.S. 664, 696 (1970)(Harlan, J. concurring)).


(Footnote 120 return)
See Kenneth Pearlman, Zoning and the Location of Religioius Establishments, 31 Cath. Law. 314, 335 (1988).


(Footnote 121 return)
120 Wash. 2d 203, 840 P.2d 174 (1992).


(Footnote 122 return)
120 Wash. 2d at 214–15, 840 P.2d 174.


(Footnote 123 return)
76 Wash. App. 572, 887 P.2d 473 (1995).


(Footnote 124 return)
See, e.g., St. Bartholomew's Church v. New York, 914 F.2d 348 (2d Cir. 1990), cert. denied, 499 U.S. 905 (1991)(sustaining a landmarking statute as a neutral and general law).


(Footnote 125 return)
Schad v. Bourough of Mt. Ephraim, 452 U.S. 61 (1981).


(Footnote 126 return)
117 S. Ct. at 2170.


(Footnote 127 return)
DePaul Survey, MQ43.


(Footnote 128 return)
See, e.g., Katzenbach v. McClung, 379 U.S. 294 (1964) (allowing Congress to impose anti-segregation laws on restaurant whose food came 46% from out-of-state); Heart of Atlanta Motel v. U.S., 379 U.S. 241 (1964) (allowing Congress to impose anti-segregation law on motel that had substantial out-of-state guests because racial discrimination in the aggregate discouraged many blacks from traveling).


(Footnote 129 return)
Jay M. Zitter, Annotation, What Constitutes Accessory or Incidental Use of Religious or Educational Property Within Zoning Ordinance, 11 A.L.R.4th 1084 (1992); Jeffrey F. Ghent, Annotation, Definition of Church or Religious Use Within Zoning Ordinances, 62 A.L.R.3d 197 (1967); Annotation, Zoning Regulations as Affecting Churches, 74 A.L.R.2d 377 (1961).


(Footnote 130 return)
A. Rathkopf & D. Rathkopf, The Law of Zoning and Planning 20 (4th ed. 1992).